Friday, January 27, 2023

The Ambiguous Violence of Culture

As I said last time, Chapter 4: "From Ressentiment to the Bad Conscience" is essentially a systematization of the three essays that compose the Genealogy of Morals.  So I felt obliged to reread the original in order to see how Deleuze's version compares.  I think it's mostly fair to say that Deleuze doesn't really add anything new to Nietzsche's scheme.  But the way he synthesizes and organizes the themes of the book, while dispensing with most of its polemic poetry, really does lend a new and not immediately obvious coherence to what Nietzsche is doing.  

The Genealogy of Morals in not intended as a realistic history of the evolution of morality, but as a schematic model of the psychological development of the human animal.  How did the animal become human?  And what type of human did it become?  We can ask these questions not only of our culture or species as a whole, but of the development of each individual psyche.  It's important to see that Nietzsche is asking a very general question about how we develop the capacity for morality, how we become a psyche capable of supporting a psychology, and not simply how we develop a particular morality or psychology, as if some definitive version of these were the 'natural' endpoint that human social evolution has been aiming at.  How did we acquire the depth, the interiority, the 'subjectivity', that can make us such an endlessly interesting animal?  Unlike every other history of humanity we've ever read, Nietzsche does not intend to take the morality and psychology of our current culture as a goal, but as a means, as a bridge to the over-human.  

4.1 

What is the difference between the active and reactive types?  Since Nietzsche's metaphysics involves only the will to power expressed through varying relations of force the answer cannot be that this one is essentially active and this other essentially reactive. In this world of ordered difference, both active and reactive must always exist as opposite sides of the same coin.  So the question is only whether the reactive forces serve the active ones, or vice versa.  Which force is on top?

The master is said to react precisely because he acts his reactions. The active type therefore includes reactive forces but ones that are defined by a capacity for obeying or being acted. The active type expresses a relation between active and reactive forces such that the latter are themselves acted. (NP, 111)

For the master, the active type, reaction still serves action.  By contrast, for the slave, the reactive type, even actions serve a reactive force.  But how can this reversal happen?  Or are we just playing with words here?  If the master, in fact, reacts and the slave also acts, how can we tell them apart?  This problem is precisely why Nietzsche introduces the term ressentimentRessentiment is the 'action' of the reactive type.  This peculiar type of action appears when the 'natural' reactions of the active type are no longer acted out or acted on.  Ressentiment stems from a block imposed on the acting of reactions.  In place of this active re-acting, we get the passive re-feeling of ressentiment

Ressentiment designates a type in which reactive forces prevail over active forces. But they can only prevail in one way: by ceasing to be acted. Above all we must not define ressentiment in terms of the strength of a reaction. If we ask what the man of ressentiment is, we must not forget this principle: he does not re-act.  And the word ressentiment gives a definite clue: reaction ceases to be acted in order to become something felt (senti). (NP, 111)

4.2

How does this blockage come about?  Deleuze gives us a very interesting account of the mechanism that casts Nietzsche's theory of ressentiment as a precursor to Freud's theory of the relations between our conscious and unconscious processes.  Consciousness is like a mobile and flexible skin that constantly receives impressions from the world.  Traces or memories of these impressions are stored in the unconscious warehouse, as it were, that our skin contains.  Consciousness, in other words, is a sort of oriented topological boundary between the world and the unconscious.  What's important about this boundary is that it normally faces outwards, towards what is happening in the present world, which permits the organism to adapt and re-act much more flexibly than a strictly unconscious process based on past memories would allow.  

The reactive unconscious is defined by mnemonic traces, by lasting imprints. It is a digestive, vegetative and ruminative system, which expresses "the purely passive impossibility of escaping from the impression once it is received" ... But the inadequacy of this first kind of reactive force is obvious. Adaptation would never be possible if the reactive apparatus did not have another system of forces at its disposal. Another system is necessary, a system in which reaction is not a reaction to traces but becomes a reaction to the present excitation or to the direct image of the object. This second kind of reactive forces is inseparable from consciousness: that constantly renewed skin surrounding an ever fresh receptivity, a milieu "where there is always room for new things". (NP, 112)

Having consciousness oriented towards the outside, towards the present, is what makes an organism's reactions suitable for action.  When reactions are triggered by current conscious impressions they'll pertain to the world at hand.  But this orientation has to be maintained by an active force of forgetting that continually empties consciousness, prepares it for new impressions, and keeps it separate from the processing of stored impressions that happens in the unconscious.  

Nietzsche defines the faculty of forgetting as "no mere vis inertiae as the superficial imagine; it is rather an active and in the strictest sense positive faculty of repression", "an apparatus of absorption", "a plastic, regenerative and curative force." Thus, there are two simultaneous processes: reaction becomes something acted because it takes conscious excitation as its object and reaction to traces remains in the unconscious, imperceptible." (NP, 113)

Forgetting (should we call it 'dropping the ball'?) is an activity, but an odd sort of activity whose function is merely to keep conscious reactions separate from unconscious reactions by constantly wiping clean the slate of consciousness.  What happens if this faculty of forgetting is disturbed?  What happens if for some reason our conscious buffer overflows or our skin hardens so that we cannot accept new impressions?  In this case, the unconscious traces that had been kept 'repressed' can rise to the surface of consciousness and displace our conscious reactions.  For fairly obvious reasons, our unconscious reactions, based on the representation of past memory traces, are less likely to be suitable for acting on.  This maladaptation to the world that results from a malfunction of forgetting is what Nietzsche calls "sickness".  The activity of our conscious reaction becomes blocked because the orientation of our conscious skin has been reversed.  This is why Deleuze calls this first aspect of ressentiment "topological".  Consciousness is now receiving impressions from within, it is re-feeling the unconscious past, instead of re-acting to the present.  

We rediscover the definition of ressentiment: ressentiment is a reaction which simultaneously becomes perceptible and ceases to be acted: a formula which defines sickness in general. Nietzsche is not simply saying that ressentiment is a sickness, but rather that sickness as such is a form of ressentiment. (NP, 114) 

4.3

Deleuze leaves the question of just exactly why the membrane of consciousness should get turned inside out in this fashion unanswered.  However, he does point out to us that it is not due to a stimulus so strong that it overpowers consciousness -- what we would today call trauma.  Some terrible pain may certainly have occurred, but this still begs the question of why the trace of this particular pain should be retained and continually resurfaced as 'trauma'.  Moreover, since Nietzsche is not (exclusively) concerned with individual psychology, he's not interested in merely tracing this illness back to a proximate cause that might explain why we reorient towards memories in the case of particular external stimuli.  What he's after is diagnosing something like a 'ressentiment syndrome' that would explain why this topological inversion persists, spreads, and even becomes a habit.  In other words, he's interested in ressentiment as a type, as a mode of being.  While his diagnosis doesn't completely answer the question of how the illness arises to begin with (we'll come back to this), it does help us see the essence of its mechanism.

Ressentiment become a type when it morphs into the habit of blame and revenge.  This habit can't be explained by the force of the external stimuli, but only by some sort of internal disruption, namely, the reorientation of consciousness.  Consciousness is a reactive force that evolved to take impressions as input from the world and give actions as output to the world.  It's almost reflective in this sense, just a thin shiny surface that quickly hooks the sensory to the motor in a manner guided by a lot of processing activity that remains unconscious.  Regardless of what metaphor we use, the most important point to emphasize is that the surface is asymmetrical -- one side reflects while the other blocks.  When the orientation of this surface gets flipped, the stimuli that come from the world no longer bounce off its external surface, so speak, but penetrate directly inside.  Traces of these are then sent back up to its internal surface, which in turn 'acts' to reflect them back inside, and etc ... The consciousness of ressentiment functions like a one way mirror that lets stimuli in, but never lets anything out, never acts.  This. Sucks.  Deleuze's point is that this syndrome is incredibly painful in itself.  The problem is not with the 'objectively' painful external stimuli.  The problem is now that we can't have done with any stimulus.  We are trapped in endless papaƱca.   Everything penetrates us and bounces around endlessly within us, even the pleasant sensations.  And what we're mainly conscious of is that we can't do anything about it.  Ressentiment is just an endless re-feeling that separates us from our ability to act and reduces our power (negative affect).  However, since we don't diagnose our illness correctly, we don't blame our selves but all these objects that keep assailing us.  Ultimately every object is to blame for our pain, even the good ones, because each one reminds us how powerless we are.  And so we end up wanting to take revenge on the whole world.  

As a result of his type the man of ressentiment does not "react": his reaction is endless, it is felt instead of being acted. This reaction therefore blames its object, whatever it is, as an object on which revenge must be taken, which must be made to pay for this infinite delay. Excitation can be beautiful and good and the man of ressentiment can experience it as such; it can be less than the force of the man of ressentiment and he can possess an abstract quantity of force as great as that of anyone else. He will none the less feel the corresponding object as a personal offense and affront because he makes the object responsible for his own powerlessness to invest anything but the trace - a qualitative or typical powerlessness. (NP, 115)

4.4 - 4.5

From this description of the mechanism of ressentiment, we can infer a number of characteristics of the illness.  First, the man of ressentiment has become "spiritual" because his consciousness faces inwards instead of outwards.  In fact, since he is unable to act, his revenge on the objects of the world is entirely imaginary.  The invention and substitution of a new interior world of the spirit is how ressentiment stabilizes itself as a habit or type.  "Spirit" actually becomes a means of taking revenge (NP, 116), though what we really triumph over is not the objects of the world but only the activity within ourselves.  Nevertheless, this imaginary or spiritual revenge still has real consequences.  The man of ressentiment is the original touchy passive aggressive type.  These unfortunate souls cannot love in the true sense of the word; nothing pleases them because everything reminds them of their powerlessness.  But they hold on to this powerlessness as if it were a power.  Because they themselves are forced to be passive, they turn this passivity into a special form of power they call 'selflessness'.  Their only action is judgement; they judge whether others are as weak and inactive as they are, because they benefit from this lack of activity.  Lack of activity is actually the only thing that benefits them.  Thus they invent morality, which is nothing more than a paean to their own weakness, a glorification of not-acting and an accusation leveled against a hostile world of activity.  Now we can see the mechanism of the dialectical inversion Deleuze introduced us to all the way back at the beginning of chapter 1.  The inversion of the orientation of consciousness means that the man of ressentiment defines himself entirely through negation.

"You are evil, therefore I am good." In this formula it is the slave who speaks. It cannot be denied that values are still being created. But what bizarre values! They begin by positing the other as evil. He who called himself good is the one who is now called evil. This evil one is the one who acts, who does not hold himself back from acting, who does not therefore consider action from the point of view of the consequences that it will have for third parties. And the one who is good is now the one who holds himself back from acting: he is good just because he refers all actions to the standpoint of the one who does not act, to the standpoint of the one who experiences the consequences, or better still to the more subtle standpoint of a divine third party who scrutinizes the intentions of the one who acts. (NP, 121)

4.6

Deleuze's description of the characteristics of ressentiment culminates in the paralogism of substance that expresses the core illusion this type needs to believe in.  Substance is just a force abstracted from its power of acting.  To invent a substance we have to imagine that things are not happening as they are.  We have to imagine that they could be different, that an active force could have not act, and that the reactive force of the man of ressentiment could have acted.  As if he would ever dream of taking your bullshit money!  Substance is just the passive neutral actor left over when we imagine away all of the real actions.  In it we see the first glimmerings of 'free will'.  The whole idea is based on the metaphysical fiction of a force separated from what it can do, a force whose power is not expressed in its actions but somehow bottled up within itself.  Obviously, the powerlessness of the man of ressentiment himself is the model for this entity.

Here we have the foundation of the paralogism of ressentiment: the fiction of a force separated from what it can do. It is thanks to this fiction that reactive forces triumph. It is not sufficient for them to hold back from activity: they must also reverse the relation of forces, they must oppose themselves to active forces and represent themselves as superior. The process of accusation in ressentiment fulfills this task: reactive forces "project" an abstract and neutralised image of force; such a force separated from its effects will be blameworthy if it acts, deserving, on the contrary, if it does not. Moreover it is thought that more (abstract) force is needed to hold back than is needed to act. (NP, 123)

Deleuze breaks this paralogism down into three stages.  

1)  We invent the idea of a causality that separates cause from effect.  In reality, what we call an effect is just an extension of a cause, just as what a force does is not separate from the force, but simply an expression of what that force is.  

Force is first repressed into itself, then its manifestation is made into a different thing which finds its distinct, efficient cause in the force. (NP, 123)

Nietzsche's metaphysics of force doesn't leave room for a force in-itself, separated from its relation to other forces.  I think the similarity to a Mahayana metaphysics of emptiness is not incidental here, nor is the similarity of Nietzsche's critique of causality to the idea of dependent origination.  Dependent origination is not the same as causality.  The 'units' that dependently arise are not substantial entities with firm boundaries, but empty phenomena that interpenetrate.  This means that the world is much much too complex for us to separate phenomena clearly enough to call one cause and the succeeding one effect.  But this complex world is still ordered, and it is ordered by whatever perspective we take on it at the moment, whatever "way of looking" we are employing.  What we normally call a cause is actually just the most salient and perhaps manipulable variable a system presents for us.  The 'cause' of the light going on is the light switch (and not the wiring, power plant, energy source, electrons, etc ...).  I think this may be what Deleuze means here.

An imaginary relation of causality is substituted for a real relation of significance. (NP, 123)

2) We project this fiction of a neutral force that may or may not act onto a substrate, which then gives us the idea of a substance or subject.  

3) We judge the quality of this force or subject not by what it does, but by what it doesn't do.  In other words we judge it morally, which is to say inversely to its actual power. 

As soon as forces are projected into a fictitious subject this subject proves to be blameworthy or deserving - blameworthy if active force performs the activity which is its own, deserving if reactive force does not perform the activity which it . . . does not have. (NP, 124)

4.7

There's a certain creativity involved in the invention of the paralogism of the moral substance.  Nietzsche attributes this creativity historically to the Jewish priests.  They were the ones who invented the fiction of a force-that-could-have-not-acted, which suddenly gives meaning to the pain of an inverted consciousness by rebranding its enforced passivity as being a force-that-could-have-acted-but-did-not.  With the intervention of the Jewish priest, the man of ressentiment no longer fights against his illness, and in fact no longer even sees it as an illness, but as a mark of his moral virtue.  The priest gives him a new story where the origin of his problem is inverted ("you are evil" -- even though it's my reactive illness causing me pain) and then projected outside himself ("therefore I am good" -- so I can feel justified in taking revenge on you).

Deleuze breaks both ressentiment and bad conscience into two aspects or moments.  The first is a "raw" of "topological" one that illustrates them as a sort of syndrome (as we saw, the reversal of the orientation of consciousness in the case of ressentiment).  The second moment develops the first in the sense that the flower 'develops' the plant.  The Jewish priest develops ressentiment by giving it a meaning, he interprets its pain as a symptom of a moral universe, thus ushering in its "typological" second moment.  In a sense, the priest actually cures the patient, though only by making the disease more intractable and invisible.  Though it's not immediately apparent, I think what Deleuze wants to convey by drawing this distinction between a first and second moment (topology and typology) is that some creative cultural intervention is necessary for these psychological quirks to become full blown types.  Some will must see the potential of these reactive forces, then organize and propagate them.  In other words, there is a will to power that makes use of the raw reactive forces, and makes them become or develop.  This is the will to power of the priest as a cultural institution.  So I think the emphasis on these two moments is our first glimpse of a problem we will return to -- the creative violence of culture.

4.8

So both ressentiment and bad conscience have a development.  But there's also a development from one to the other.  Bad conscience is the next natural development after the triumph of ressentiment orchestrated by the Jewish priest.  With his success, ressentiment permanently and characteristically blocks the activity of the organism and separates it from what it can do.  Which is to say that the formerly active forces have become reactive.  Deleuze has already shown us how this development works.  In becoming-reactive, active forces turn back against themselves and carry out the only 'activity' left to them -- rattling the bars of their cage.

... whatever the reason that an active force is falsified, deprived of its conditions of operation and separated from what it can do, it is turned back inside, turned back against itself. Being interiorised, being turned back against itself - this is the way in which active force becomes truly reactive. "All instincts that do not discharge themselves outwardly turn inward - that is what I call the intemalisation of man . . . that is the origin of the 'bad conscience' (NP, 127)

With this new development, the evil and pain that ressentiment formerly projected outside itself, is now taken back insideI become evil, I become the source of the problem.  This isn't the opposite of ressentiment, but it's further development, the way it spreads its contagion of reactivity and poisons every active force.

In ressentiment reactive force accuses and projects itself. But ressentiment would be nothing if it did not lead the accused himself to admit his wrongs, to "turn back to himself: the introjection of active forces is not the opposite of projection but the consequence and the continuation of reactive projection. (NP, 128)

We've seen how ressentiment was already full of pain.  Everything is painful to this type because it merely reinforces its inability to re-act to the world.  The Jewish priest provides a cure for this pain by attributing it to evil forces outside of us.  Of course, like all good pharmaceutical business models, we can never finish taking this 'cure'.  Whatever new stimulus comes along will also be painful, because ultimately we have misdiagnosed the problem.  But with the development of bad conscience, and the introjection of the source of the pain, our suffering can now multiply endlessly.  We don't even need the world anymore, we can make ourselves suffer.  "It's your fault" becomes "it's my fault".

The multiplication of pain by the interiorisation or introjection of force — this is the first definition of bad conscience. (NP, 129)

4.9 

Here Deleuze inserts a short chapter on "The Problem of Pain".  This actually interrupts the main thrust of the story of how bad conscience develops out of ressentiment.  The aim is to contrast the way that bad conscience blames pain on something within us with an interpretation that gives pain a meaning external to us.  Of course, one might at first wonder how this latter would be any different than the developed form of ressentiment, which already seemed to blame our pain on external evils.  The key difference lies in the word blame.  What Deleuze has in mind with an external meaning of pain is essentially the tragic interpretation of life, that doesn't see pain as the ground for an accusation of life at all, regardless of whether the blame should be directed externally or internally.  What if pain doesn't come from an external object or an internal subject, but simply happens as a byproduct of the fact that we are small and the universe is big?  What happens to our idea of pain if no one is to blame for it? 

There are a couple of ways Deleuze answer's this question that don't seem to fit together in my mind.  What if pain is simply a sign that we should do something differently?  In this case, no one is to blame for our pain, and in a way it becomes a fairly meaningless trigger for action.  It just results from the fact that our tiny organism is in ongoing unstable interaction with a great big world.  Deleuze might be alluding to this interpretation here.  Perhaps every pain a reactive force feels is a pleasure for the active force that dominates it?

Now, pain is a reaction. Thus it appears that its only meaning consists in the possibility of acting this reaction or at least of localising it, isolating its trace, in order to avoid all propagation until one can re-act once more. (NP, 129)

Another possibility is that our pain is a mere byproduct in a different sense -- it happens to give pleasure to the gods who watch our actions as we would watch a drama.  

The masters have a secret. They know that pain has only one meaning: giving pleasure to someone, giving pleasure to someone who inflicts or contemplates pain. If the active man is able not to take his own pain seriously it is because he always imagines someone to whom it gives pleasure. It is not for nothing that such an imagination is found in the belief in the active gods which peopled the Greek world: " 'Every evil the sight of which edifies a god is justified'. . . what was at bottom the ultimate meaning of Trojan Wars and other such tragic terrors? There can be no doubt whatever: they were intended as festival plays for the gods" (NP, 129)
 
While the particular violent Greek version of this idea may not resonate with us, perhaps we can imagine that our pain is somehow necessary as part of the increase in power (ie. pleasure) of some much larger force.  Looked at from this larger, tragic, perspective, our pain is not a problem with life, but part of its cosmic drama, so to speak.  If we were able to identify with this larger force, perhaps it wouldn't feel like pain at all?  

The problem of pain is a deep one that we may have to come back to at the end of the chapter.  It relates to the violence of culture that we will discuss beginning in 4.11.  The overarching idea seems to be the life is somehow always cutting into itself as a means of developing.  As if there were a larger Life that proceeds only at the cost of producing and destroying many small lives.  Perhaps this larger Life experiences a sort of pleasure in channeling itself into particular forms?  The tree of life enjoys pruning itself?  This would be related to the selective power of the eternal return, which works through what one might call a violent method where the negative destroys itself.  

4.10

When the force that causes pain is no longer projected outside of us but introjected inside of us, we move from the developed (typological) form of ressentiment to the undeveloped (topological) form of bad conscience.  The Jewish 'cure' for pain has been reversed.  In a sense, this reversal is a more accurate diagnosis of the pain of ressentiment, which, after all, does stem from a disturbance within the organism and not fundamentally from external objects.  As this reversal of a reversal develops however, we move from simply placing the substance causing pain within us to actually identifying with that substance.  The thing causing us pain isn't simply inside, it's us, some fault in us, some sin.  Historically, this development of bad conscience is guided by the Christian priest, who continues the reactive trajectory of the Jewish priest by reversing the direction of ressentiment.  

"If one wanted to express the value of the priestly existence in the briefest formula it would be: the priest alters the direction of ressentiment" (GM III 15 p. 127). It will be recalled that the man of ressentiment, who is by nature full of pain, is looking for a cause for his suffering. He accuses, he accuses everything that is active in life. The priest appears in an initial [Jewish] form here: he presides over the accusation, he organises it. "Look at these men who call themselves good, I tell you: these are the evil ones." The power of ressentiment is therefore completely directed towards the other, against others. But ressentiment is an explosive substance: it makes active forces become reactive. Ressentiment must then adapt itself to these new conditions; it must change direction. The reactive man must now find the cause of his suffering in himself. Bad conscience suggests to him that he must look for this cause "in himself, in some guilt, in a piece of the past, he must understand his suffering as a punishment" (GM III 20 p. 140). And the priest appears a second time [now Christian] in order to preside over this change of direction: "Quite so, my sheep! someone must be to blame for it - you alone are to blame for yourself." (GM III 15 p. 128). The priest invents the notion of sin.  (NP, 131)

One interesting aspect of this story is the way it makes Christianity the natural outgrowth of Judaism not just historically, but typologically.  It's like watching the progression of an underlying disease from one state to another.  With the help of the Jewish priest, the reactive forces of ressentiment actually triumph over active forces.  Ressentiment separates active force from what it can do and makes it become reactive.  It produces a 'good' and powerless slave surrounded by 'evil' and hated masters.  If this were the final state of the disease it would be pretty harmless though.  It's obvious that this sort of thinking is only likely to catch on amongst those who feel themselves oppressed.  It converts their powerlessness, their very oppression, into a sign of distinction (the chosen people).  If this disease spreads, however, more and more formerly active oppressors are made to become reactive as well.  The remaining targets of ressentiment begin to diminish.  Who is left to do all the oppressing if all the active forces have become reactive?  If we aren't oppressing ourselves, we can't all become slaves.  Conversely, if the evil one is within us, literally everyone can suffer from the disease. This is the historical genius of the Christian priest, who makes the illness of ressentiment metastasize.  

But, once again, it should not be thought that the new direction of ressentiment in bad conscience is opposed to the first direction. Once again, we are merely concerned with an additional temptation, an additional seduction. Ressentiment said "it is your fault", bad conscience says "it is my fault". But ressentiment is really only appeased when its contagion is spread. Its aim is for the whole of life to become reactive, for those in good health to become sick. It is not enough for it to accuse, the accused must feel guilty. (NP, 132)

 4.11 - 4.13

With these three subsections Deleuze launches into the lengthy digression foreshadowed in 4.9.  They deal with the meaning of culture.  Culture, for Nietzsche, has to do with training and selection.  This may seem a slightly odd definition at first.  But I think what Deleuze is getting at here is something we're all familiar with.  Consider the sort of self-selection that establishes and maintains the culture of any group.  Tech culture.  College culture.  Church culture.  Mediation culture.  'Western culture'.  These cultures have a shaping or pruning effect.  They are larger forces that selectively cultivate a certain type of individual by elevating some and demoting others.  Those who partially fit in are made to fit in better, and those who don't are encouraged to leave.  Of course, no one is in charge of these cultures.  They have a momentum of their own created by the interaction of the participants.  But they operate almost as if they had a goal, as if there were some force making a selection.

When Nietzsche talks about Culture, however, he does not have any of these specific cultures in mind, but something more like the capacity to form these cultures.  'Human Culture' selects for individuals capable of participating in these other cultures.  As we alluded to at the beginning of this post, it's really what makes us human.  It produces the possibility of interaction that enables us to form specific cultural groups.  This is why Deleuze will call it our "species activity".  He will treat the phenomenon of culture from three points of view -- the prehistoric, the post-historic, and the historic -- which roughly correspond to the means, the end, and the perversion of culture.

The means of culture are violence.  Prehistory is, "soaked in blood thoroughly and for a long time." (GM, 2.6, pg 65)  Nietzsche believes that this pain is necessary to train our reactive forces in such a way that they can acted.  We have to be trained to obey something called 'the law'.  This isn't any particular law, but simply the principle of the submission of our reactive forces to some more powerful active force.  

Every historical law is arbitrary, but what is not arbitrary, what is prehistoric and generic, is the law of obeying laws. ... Prehistoric means generic. Culture is man's prehistoric activity. But what does this activity consist in? It is always a matter of giving man habits, of making him obey laws, of training him. Training man means forming him in such a way that he can act his reactive forces.  The activity of culture is, in principle, exercised on reactive forces, it gives them habits and imposes models on them in order to make them suitable for being acted. (NP, 133)

A casual reader might imagine that Nietzsche is saying something similar to Hobbes.  In order for the individual to exist in society, he has to give up the gratification of his impulses and submit to the law of the state.  Life in pre-history was nasty, brutish, and short, but thankfully the training and self-domestication of culture made all that avoidable.  This is precisely what Nietzsche is not saying.  Hobbes (like almost all philosophers) takes as his starting point of civilization someone very much like himself -- a fully formed individual who knows what they want and is capable of controlling their desires.  Hobbes' sovereign individual may have all sorts of anti-social designs on his neighbor's wife, but he is already innately capable of submitting to his own reason, which of course famously counseled him that it would be smarter to enter into a social contract than to fix the cable.  But this begs Nietzshe's question: how did someone capable of following a law -- of giving and then following even his own law -- come to exist?  Culture, for Nietzsche, is what creates such an individual from the animal.  This is what it means to act our reactions, to become active and able to make our own (or perhaps in the initial phase our culture's) choices.  Hobbes' subject isn't prehistoric at all, but a projection of himself into the past.  His starting point is for Nietzsche the end product of culture.

This is precisely the selective object of culture: forming a man capable of promising and thus of making use of the future, a free and powerful man. Only such a man is active; he acts his reactions, everything in him is active or acted. The faculty of promising is the effect of culture as the activity of man on man; the man who can promise is the product of culture as species activity. (NP, 134)

The violence of culture isn't necessary in order to enforce a social contract or keep people from running through the streets raping and pillaging.  It's necessary to create a human animal that can remember its promises, and hence control its future self.  Nietzsche claims that the model for this inter-temporal structure within an individual is the debtor-creditor relationship between individuals.  And he sees this latter relation as a fundamentally violent one where pain becomes the medium of exchange used to settle debts.  Pain seems to be the only stimulus strong enough to train us to abide by credit contracts, including the contract with our future self.  

This adds a new nuance to the problem of pain that arose in 4.9.  Nietzsche seems to believe that the debtor's pain is the creditor's pleasure.  This is the unavoidable logic of making pain a medium of exchange.  If the training of culture merely depended on the way it teaches us to keep our promises so that we avoid pain, we would be left unable to explain the mechanism which inflicts this pain in the case of a broken promise.  In other words, it's easy to see the selective effect of pain, but it's hard to understand the cause that's doing the selecting.   For pain to work as a consistent, long-term training mechanism in a society, someone has to play the role of enforcer.  But what do they get out of this role?  Do they inflict pain as punishment for broken promises out of some altruistic concern for the 'good of the whole'?  Nietzsche would consider this answer a moralistic evasion.  Whether the enforcer, the causer of pain, is one person or the whole group acting in concert, it seems that there must be some sort of pleasure in inflicting pain, precisely the pleasure of a superior force dominating a weaker one.  The equation of my pain with someone else's pleasure, or the equation: "injury caused = pain undergone" (NP, 134), is exactly what Deleuze meant when he talked about the external meaning of pain. Culture is external to us.  As a more powerful force, it uses the medium of pain to train our capacity to eventually discipline ourselves.  We have to imagine that, from the perspective of this culture, our pain is part of a larger pleasure, perhaps analogous to the way the enforced stunting of a bonsai produces a beautiful shape. 

The point of emphasizing this at first somewhat repellent interpretation of pain is to distinguish it from the interpretation that ressentiment and bad conscience provide.  Their pain, for these reactive types of consciousness, is always an unequivocally bad thing that should be made to stop.  This is the understandable perspective of someone weak and ill and in constant pain.  But of course it's also somewhat ironic because the reactive type runs from a Jewish ressentiment that 'cures' pain only by constantly looking for things to kvetch about, to a Christian bad conscience that multiplies pain by making it our own fault.  In either case, the meaning of pain is internal, and the opposite of pain isn't pleasure, but just not-pain.  Pain, for the reactive man is fundamentally a breakdown of justice, a malfunction in the universe, something that shouldn't be happening, something that he would like, but can never get, revenge for.  It's the unanswerable crux of the problem of evil -- if God is so great, why do I feel so miserable?  This contrasts with the perspective of the active man produced by culture.  He knows that his pain is meaningful because it is a necessary part of the universe, even, from some larger perspective, a source of pleasure.  This is the tragic worldview that doesn't try to make pain stop, but affirms it joyously.  For him, justice lies in everything being correctly ordered, according to its power, which he knows at times will involve his painful submission to the 'higher power' of culture.

On the one hand, revenge and ressentiment are not the origin of justice. Moralists, even socialist ones, make justice derive from a reactive feeling, from deeply felt offense, a spirit of revenge or justiciary reaction. But such a derivation explains nothing it would have to show how the pain of others can be a satisfaction of revenge, a reparation for revenge. We will never understand the cruel equation "injury caused = pain undergone" if a third term is not introduced - the pleasure which is felt in inflicting pain or in contemplating it. But this third term, the external meaning of pain, has an origin which is completely different from revenge or reaction: it reflects an active standpoint, active forces, which are given the training of reactive forces as their task and for their pleasure. (NP, 135)

 We might reduce this idea to a formula: justice is not about righting a wrong, but creating a right, an ability.  The active justice of culture is fundamentally opposed to the reactive morality of ressentiment and bad conscience.

But just at the moment we're highlighting the difference between these two complexes, some ambiguities start to creep into the story.  The first is an ambiguity within culture itself.  The ultimate goal of the species activity of culture is to produce an individual.  The post-historic end of the active and selective force of culture is to dissolve itself by being internalized in the active person who can self-select and self-discipline their reactions.  

The finished product of species activity isnot the responsible man himself or the moral man, but the autonomous and supramoral man, that is to say the one who actually acts his reactive forces and in whom all reactive forces are acted. He alone "is able to" promise, precisely because he is no longer responsible to any tribunal. The product of culture is not the man who obeys the law, but the sovereign and legislative individual who defines himself by power over himself, over destiny, over the law: the free, the light, the irresponsible. (NP, 137)

In essence, through a process of 'acculturation', we become the larger force of our culture.  Once we are capable of giving ourselves our own laws, we no longer need the law.  Culture overcomes itself in a "self destruction of justice".  This is how a true individual is produced as the end of history, precisely the sovereign individual Hobbes' put at the beginning of history.

The second ambiguity creeps in during history.  This is the necessary perversion of culture and confusion between it and reactive institutions.  For Nietzsche, the violence of culture is always being made to serve other ends, and 'history' is the history of the degradation of culture as a force.  The selective pressure of culture gets weaker and weaker over time precisely because it succeeds in making us so thoroughly capable of joining groups.  In this way we turn over further selection to the particular ends of each group, and no longer create the 'generic' individual that is effectively a group of one (our internalized debtor-creditor relation).  This is why Nietzsche is always so obsessed with the concept of decadence.  The more effective culture is, the more it loses its way.  The more power we have, the more stupidity we permit ourselves, the more we can survive.  In practice, our culture seems to have selected not for the sovereign individual or law-giver, but for the domestic herd animal or law-taker.  

Species activity in history is inseparable from a movement which perverts it and its product. Furthermore, history is this very perversion, it is identical to the "degeneration of culture". - Instead of species activity, history presents us with races, peoples, classes, Churches and States. Onto species activity are grafted social organisations, associations, communities of a reactive character, parasites which cover it over and absorb it. By means of species activity - the movement of which they falsify - reactive forces form collectivities, what Nietzsche calls "herds" (GM III 18). - Instead of justice and its process of self-destruction, history presents us with societies which have no wish to perish and which cannot imagine anything superior to their own laws. (NP, 138)

With decadence, culture doesn't dissolve or disappear into the individual, but becomes all pervasive.  Today we are enmeshed in so many cultures that commanding our self seems impossible.

4.14

At this point we return to the main story of the chapter, which is the genealogy of morals.  The story so far is: 1) Ressentiment arises as a disturbance of the faculty of forgetting that results in a reorientation of consciousness.  2) Ressentiment develops through the creative intervention of the Jewish priest, who gives meaning to the pain caused by that disturbance.  Your pain proves that 'they' are bad, and as a result, you are good.  You feel much better after hearing this even though you are still in pain, because now you can at least dream of revenge, even if you cannot act on it because you remain sick and powerless.  3) Bad conscience develops out of ressentiment when the source of the pain formerly projected onto the world becomes introjected inside us.  We thus multiply our own pain because what we hate and define ourselves against has moved within us.  4) Bad conscience develops into guilt and sin through the creative intervention of the Christian priest.  The thing that is giving us pain and that we are trained to hate, is actually our self.  We have some original defect or sin that makes all of our pain our own fault.  

We can see that there are two creative moments in this story.  In the first, the Jewish priest invents the fiction of an inactive force, the paralogism of the moral substance we explored in 4.6.  In the second, the Christian priest invents the notion of the super-ego, the moral conscience that causes pain from within and can never be assuaged by our actions.  We saw in 4.10 that his second moment reverses the direction of the ressentiment developed in the first moment.  We move from reactively hating a source of pain projected outside ourselves, to actively hating a source of pain within ourselves.  While this sounds understandable at first, the more you think about it, the more mysterious the psychology of this reversal becomes.  Blaming our pain on another seems like a straightforward misdiagnosis.  And at least hating them gives us a way to feel superior about our inferiority.  But why would we continually multiply our pain by blaming it on ourselves?  What belief would induce us to internalize the source of our pain and not merely separate our active force from what it can do by giving it an imaginary revenge, but actually make active force become-reactive, and start taking revenge on itself?

The long digression on the operation of culture was meant to answer this question.  Separately from the story of the genealogy of morals, a historic story, there is a story of the violent prehistory and self-overcoming post-history of culture.  Culture instills in us the model of the debtor-creditor relationship whose power asymmetry is expressed in the fact that the pain of one serves as the pleasure of the other.  In fact, this debtor-creditor relationship is really the model of what a will is -- a force operating on another force, necessarily creating a hierarchy of power.  At first, this relationship is between one person and another more power one.  Later it characterizes the relationship between the person and the larger power of the group.  Nietzsche traces the evolution of the power we are each indebted to in his second essay; it grows as the power of our collective culture grows.  We move from being in debt to another person, to being in debt to our ancestors, to being in debt to God.  The debt moves from being something we can potentially discharge through our pain, to being infinite and unpayable.  Finally, Christianity lodges the never satisfied creditor directly within us.  What we're seeing here is the gradual hijacking of the mechanism of culture by the reactive force of ressentiment.  This is what enables reactive force to not merely triumph but to spread and make everything become-reactive.  And this hijacking explains what we get from locating the source of pain within us -- it gives us pleasure.  

Christianity holds a distorted mirror up to the goal of culture.  Culture has trained us to see inflicting pain as a type of pleasure.  But it did this only as a means of forming an individual who goes beyond pleasure and pain, who so internalizes the debtor-creditor relationship that they no longer need it to govern their actions.  By contrast, Christianity internalizes the most extreme form of the creditor -- God.  Instead of merging debtor and creditor, discharging our debt to ourself and making our own law, we are now condemned to pay interest to ourselves ad infinitum, simultaneously inflicting pain on ourselves and feeling the pleasure this gives us, the "voluptuousness of the martyr" (WP, #417).  

4.15 - 4.16

One of Deleuze's goals in telling this rather elaborate story of crossbreeding is to show the moments where some creative will is required.  Someone ("which one?") has to invent the two fictions that allow ressentiment and bad conscience to respectively develop into their higher forms.  Ressentiment needed the fiction of substance.  Bad conscience needed the fiction of an internal 'higher power' (for which is borrowed and repurposed the violent means of culture).  Together, these two fictions constitute a third -- the ascetic ideal.  Or perhaps it would be more accurate to say that these two fictions are forms invented by a single underlying will (ie. a force that operates on other forces and makes them become).  Ultimately, our story revolves around the will to negate this world, to long for a better world beyond.  The weak always want things to be some other way.  As Nietzsche says in the final line of the Genealogy of Morals, in its depths, this will would rather will nothingness than will things to stay as they are ... to not will. 

In its initial sense the ascetic ideal designates the complex of ressentiment and bad conscience: it crosses the one with the other, it reinforces the one with the other. Secondly, it expresses all the ways in which the sickness of ressentiment, the suffering of bad conscience become livable, or rather, are organised and propagated; the ascetic priest is simultaneously gardener, breeder, shepherd and doctor. Finally, and this is its deepest sense, the ascetic ideal expresses the will which makes reactive forces triumph. "The ascetic ideal expresses a will" (GM III 23). We discover the idea of a fundamental complicity (not an identity, but a complicity) between reactive forces and a form of the will to power. Reactive forces would never prevail without a will which develops the projections, which organises the necessary fictions. (NP, 144)

Saturday, January 21, 2023

A History of the Apocalypse

I've long intended to write a book with this title, so I'm not surprised that several people have already beat me to it.  Since my own version will obviously never exist, I propose to follow in the footsteps of the great Stanislaw Lem and just give a brief summary and review of this non-existent book.  This only seems like a tangent to our discussion of Nietzsche & Philosophy.  In fact, the thesis of my forthcoming non-existent book is a direct application of Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals, and the fourth chapter of Deleuze's book (From Ressentiment to Bad Conscience) is clearly an attempt to (further) systematize Nietzsche's "most systematic book". (NP, 87)

I realized this morning, while reading that stentorian apologist for our current religion of growth, that the essence of apocalyptic thinking is actually quite straightforward.  The idea of the apocalypse is a perfect expression of the will to nothingness -- nihilism.  It flourishes amongst those who consider their times degenerate, and it expresses a desire (consciously or not) for those times to end.  Apocalyptic thinking stems from a desperate desire for change coupled with a perception of its impossibility.  It's the final refuge of a life or culture that has exhausted all its forces of creation and re-creation.  As a result, whatever the new mystic state believers imagine to follow the apocalypse, the important point is that the only way there is through death, through a total sweeping away of the degenerate, but nevertheless tenacious, structure of the present times.  The apocalypse is a curious case of life trying to renew itself by destroying itself, a paradox which accounts for the fact that, while the focus is always on the impending doom, we actually long for the apocalypse as salvation.  This paroxysm of fear contains a secret joy.  The world deserves to end.

Or as Nietzsche put it: "Life against life" (NP, 96).  Apocalyptic thinking is the purest expression of the ascetic ideal that he examines in the third essay of the Genealogy of Morals.  The ascetic ideal is the symptom of a sick, exhausted, and suffering life reduced to a will to nothingness -- but this is still a will!   As Deleuze points out countless times, even the negative will is a still a will to power.  The only force that can be turned against life as a whole is a particular type of life; the world beyond is always fabricated to serve ends within this world.  This is why the ascetic ideal always plays such an ambiguous role in Nietzsche's thinking.  On the one hand, it is the great enemy that he tracks through all its various incarnations -- Judaism, Christianity, Platonism, Science, even Atheism (GM, 3.27).  On the other hand, he can't help but admire the inventiveness of a type of life that at first seems to have painted itself into a corner.  And not just admire it -- it often seems as if the ascetic ideal is for Nietzsche not only a necessary step in some abstract path of spiritual development, but the very core of his own experience, as if the enemy he were fighting were really himself, or his own shadow.  He himself is, after all, heir apparent to the long tradition of degeneration that he believes characterizes the entire history of Western culture.  And yet he is uncompromisingly hard on the decadence he discovers within himself.  It would be hard to find a life more dedicated to the ascetic ideal of philosophy than Nietzsche's.  The man literally thought himself to death.  But at the same time it would be hard to find any greater critic of the self-denying "virtues" embodied in this ideal.  He understood the drives beneath this ideal of renunciation so thoroughly, that he ended up using it for precisely the opposite purpose from the one it normally serves.  Nietzsche makes the ascetic ideal a means by which a powerful and active life cuts into itself and destroys the negative within itself, rather than the endpoint of a diminished and reactive life trying to preserve itself at its lowest level.  As we've seen now many times over the past year, he takes nihilism all the way to the limit where it overcomes itself.  He lives through his own apocalypse.

Nietzsche understood, having lived it himself, what consti­tutes the mystery of a philosopher's life. The philosopher appro­priates the ascetic virtues - humility, poverty, chastity - and makes them serve ends completely his own, extraordinary ends that are not very ascetic at all; in fact. (SPP, 3)

 

Sunday, January 8, 2023

The Unlived Life is Not Worth Examing

Having explored the way Nietzschean critique radically extends the Kantian version of it, in what remains of the chapter (3.11-3.15), Deleuze returns to the question that motivated it -- which one values truth?  What type of will to power is the will to truth?  We've already seen the preliminary answer: the will to truth is a will to stop, to limit.  It's the expression of a reactive life at the service of a negative will to power.  Now, however, using the framework he built up in discussing the theory of the will to power and the eternal return, Deleuze will trace the genealogy of this will much more carefully.  And then he will show us how our thinking can escape the purported obviousness of a desire for truth.  He will show us how we can think differently -- which is to say do philosophy -- not by refuting the idea of truth, but by carrying it so far that it self-destructs.  At that extreme point, the power of thinking previously defined as a will to truth transmutes itself into art.  

3.11

Deleuze interprets the three essays in the Genealogy of Morals as dramatizing (that is, providing an answer to who or which one, which type or role) three successively deeper wills to power that lie behind the will to truth.  

1) At first, it seems the one who wills truth wills not to be deceived by the world.  The unstated presumption here is that it is 'better' not to be deceived; that being deceived leads to bad things happening.    

But this hypothesis presupposes the truthfulness of the world itself. For, in a radically false world it is the will to not let oneself be deceived that becomes inauspicious, dangerous and harmful. In fact, the will to truth had to be formed "in spite of the danger and the uselessness of the truth at any price". (NP, 95)

In fact, even a quick examination of our 'highest', most scientific, truths reveals that they don't do much of anything for us on an everyday basis or without the backing of an enormous technical, political, and social machine.  Do you fall down less because you know the floor is 'really' made of atoms?  In practice, 'the truth' is often the furthest things from what is beneficial.  So the will to truth cannot piggyback off the obviousness of will to the 'good' (which, as we saw, still begs the question of who benefits from the good).

2) Maybe, then, the will to truth is motivated by the will to not deceive.  Not being deceived would then be the special case of not wanting to deceive yourself.  This reverses the assumptions of the first will because it presumes that the world is always giving us false appearances, and that we'll be better off if we separate out some true reality.  Clearly, this will introduces a metaphysical appearance/reality dualism, a dualism that Nietzsche will always trace back to a moral will.  The will to not deceive is a will to correct life with knowledge, to improve or purify a dirty, sordid, and deceitful existence.  Here we can start to clearly see that a will to truth based on a will to not deceive is the opposite of the tragic perspective.  It accuses life of making mistakes and blames it for our suffering.  

The man who does not want to deceive wants a better world and a better life; all his reasons for not deceiving are moral ones. And we always come up against the virtuism of the one who wills the truth: one of his favourite occupations is the distribution of wrongs, he renders responsible, he denies innocence, he accuses and judges life, he denounces appearance. (NP, 96)

3) Nevertheless, while the will to not deceive wants a better version of life, distinct from everything it sees around it, it is and remains a will that operates from within this life.  The better, more truthful world it posits is, after all, a fiction.  The desire to substitute this fiction for real life and call it truth is actually just a symptom of a desire for life to stop, or at least be made as small as possible.  The positive aspiration towards truth masks a negative desire to reduce a life that is considered error. 

The one who wants another world, another life, wants something more profound: "Life against life" (GM III 13 p. 120). He wants life to become virtuous, to correct itself and to correct appearance, for it to serve as the way to the other world. He wants life to repudiate itself and to turn against itself (NP, 96)

At its deepest level the will to truth is a symptom of the oldest religious belief -- the ascetic ideal.  It's an attempt to purifying away life itself.  Which, since it can only originate from within life, is a symptom of the weakest type of life, one that can only survive by making itself as small as possible.  This type of life is an unholy marriage of reactive forces and the negative will to power, the will to nothingness.  It sees even its own life as nothing but suffering, but hasn't the guts to end it all, so merely imagines itself fading to nothing, 'transcending' this world while remaining in it.  This is the kind of life that values only truth, and the value of truth for this life lies in the way it saves life by limiting it to its lowest level.  The ascetic ideal is a will to nothingness that, because it is wielded by a reactive force, is not carried to its limit.

In fact, it is not the will which is denied in superior values [like truth], it is the superior values that are related to a will to deny, to annihilate life. This will to deny defines "the value" of superior values. Its weapon is to hand life over to the domination of reactive forces in such a way that the whole of life slips further and further away, separated from what it can do, getting smaller and smaller, towards nothingness, "towards the poignant feeling of his nothingness" (GM III 25). The will to nothingness and reactive forces, these are the two constituent elements of the ascetic ideal. (NP, 97)

These three steps form the genealogy of the will to truth, and correspond to the three parts of the Genealogy of Morals -- knowledge (will to truth) stems from morality (the will to the good) which is a branch of religion (the incomplete and reactive will to nothingness, to the divine, the ascetic ideal). 

3.12

The genealogy of truth can be read in either direction.  So far we've traced back from someone who says they value truth to the ascetic will to power that gives truth a value.  Read in the forward direction, however, it provides a description of the cultural evolution from religion to morality to knowledge.  We no longer believe in the ascetic ideals of religion.  We don't even buy into an absolute morality stripped of religious sentiment.  But we certainly still believe in the truth -- we just call it science now.  

Let us for a moment turn our attention to evolution instead of genealogy: let us descend again from the ascetic or religious ideal to the will to truth. We must then acknowledge that morality has replaced religion as a dogma and that science is increasingly replacing morality. (NP, 97)

When we see where the value of truth came from, it turns out to be pretty easy to uncover the ascetic ideal latent in our scientific worldview.  Consider how often you've heard the 'truth' that we are nothing but an unremarkable chemical reaction strutting on and fretting about a pretty typical planet orbiting a third rate star in one of innumerable galaxies.  In other words, the scientists are always telling us that we must accept that we are objectively nothing.  On the other hand, we should bow to their objectivity and use the tools of truth to stay as comfortable as possible and live our nothingness for as long as we can.  It's a deeply conservative message when you think about it (even though in USA 2023 we would associate this belief in science with a liberal politics).  Even though they're proving to us every day that we are not the center of the universe, we are not rational, and we are not even the supreme intelligence, we're supposed to just carry on as before.  It's almost enough to make you think there is a global milk conspiracy

What should we do, however, when we discover that our will to truth is simply a will to preserve the lowest type of life?  Does Nietzsche have some new ideal to fill the place successively occupied by the divine, the good, and the true?  Of course not.  Nietzsche knows as well as anyone the trajectory he himself is heir to.  He understands it, feels it, so thoroughly that he wants to take it to its limit.  He wants the will to nothingness in the ascetic ideal to become active.  He wants to carry through with this will, make it break its alliance reactive forces that limit it and preserve the lowest type of life.  In short, he wants to force the ascetic ideal to self destruct.  This is the secret to the meaning of the eternal return as a selective (a self-selective) doctrine.  It's actually a religious doctrine taken to its extreme point, where the will to nothingness becomes so pure that it destroys the reactive forces and transmutes into a becoming-active.  Nietzsche continues the genealogy of the will to truth in the same direction, and leads nihilism to the point where it overcomes itself.  And then we are free.  

When we denounce the permanence of the ascetic ideal in the will to truth we deprive this ideal of the condition of its permanence or its final disguise. In this sense we too are "truthful" or "seekers after knowledge".  But we do not replace the ascetic ideal, we let nothing of the place itself remain, we want to destroy the place, we want another ideal in another place, another way of knowing, another concept of truth, that is to say a truth which is not presupposed in a will to truth but which presupposes a completely different will. (NP, 99)

3.13

One of the rather obscure themes running through Zarathustra is an ambiguous conflict between, and similarity of, wisdom and life.  In this subsection Deleuze attempts to clarify their relationship.  We've seen how knowledge, if it is based on a will to truth, is always in service of reactive forces.  It represents an incomplete will to nothingness that preserves life by limiting it.  For Nietzsche and Deleuze, what we call reason or rational knowledge is nothing but a type of thought that disciplines both thought and life.  

Knowledge is opposed to life, but because it expresses a life which contradicts life, a reactive life which finds in knowledge a means of preserving and glorifying its type. (Thus knowledge gives life laws that separate it from what it can do, that keep it from acting, that forbid it to act, maintaining it in the narrow framework of scientifically observable reaction: almost like an animal in a zoo. But this knowledge that measures, limits and moulds life is itself entirely modelled on reactive life, within the limits of reactive life.) (NP, 100)

By contrast, an affirmative thought would seek to overcome the limits that reactive life sets on itself.  In fact, in a sense, affirmative thought -- that is to say, critique taken to its active limit -- is not different than an affirmative, tragic, type of life.  These two affirmations would act like continuations of one another.  Instead of reactive life producing a negative and limiting rational thought that only serves to police the limits life 'must' set on itself, an affirmative life produces an affirmative thought that shows this same life new possibilities for living, and thinking, ad infinitum.  

A thought that would go to the limit of what life can do, a thought that would lead life to the limit of what it can do? A thought that would affirm life instead of a knowledge that is opposed to life. Life would be the active force of thought, but thought would be the affirmative power of life. Both would go in the same direction, carrying each other along, smashing restrictions, matching each other step for step, in a burst of unparalleled creativity. Thinking would then mean discovering, inventing, new possibilities of life. " (NP, 101)

This helps us understand the ambiguity in Zarathustra.  When Nietzsche uses the word "wisdom" he can mean either of these types of thinking, depending on the context.  One type of wisdom, which Deleuze usually calls "knowledge" or "rationality", only serves reactive life and is opposed to an affirmative type of life.  Another type, which Deleuze calls "thought" or "art", extends an active life and only opposes reactive forces that limit what life can do.  In each case, we get the type of wisdom, the type of thinking, that corresponds to and reinforces our type of life.  The idea that there is an opposition between thought and life actually mixes the two viewpoints.  

[I don't have a complete theory that maps the ambiguities in TSZ onto Deleuze's schema.  But I note that there are two chapters that center on the relationship between, and even the confusion of, Life and Wisdom -- 2.10 The Dance Song and 3.15 The Other Dance Song.  These two chapters refer internally to one another, as well as to 1.18 On Old and Young Little Women, which contains that famous line about "not forgetting the whip".  It can't be coincidence that all of these chapters deal with women, which of course for Nietzsche is a synonym for deception.  If we consider that though and life are almost two forms of a positive power of deception, we might genuinely start to wonder if Nietzsche's misogyny is as simple as it appears to be.  In a book whose deepest teaching is the interconversion of opposites, we shouldn't be too surprised to find that male and female are only apparently in opposition.]

3.14

Art is another word for the type of thinking that expresses an active, creative, and affirmative will to power.  Deleuze, clearly intends the term broadly, with philosophy counted as a form of conceptual art.  The will to art is the 'opposite' of the will to truth.  Truth we imagine as some objective universal that can only be approached by a disinterested observer.  We like to think we don't create truth, we simply discover it.  By contrast, art is created through the interests of an active life, and only fully appreciated when we are drawn into the life of the artist (not so much the biographical life, but the process of creation).  Art is also the 'opposite' of knowledge in that it embodies a positive will to falsehood as opposed to a will to truth.  Art celebrates its own semblance, and thereby affirms the creative power of life. 

The second principle of art is as follows: art is the highest power of falsehood, it magnifies the "world as error", it sanctifies the lie; the will to deception is turned into a superior idea. (NP, 102)

Which is to say that art is the product of nihilism overcoming itself.  Art is the becoming-active of the previously reactive forces of thought and life.  Here we see the same structure of selection or cultivation we saw with the eternal return.  No force simply is active, but forces can become-active.  When the negative power of life becomes active and self-destructs, the will to truth is transmuted into a positive will to deceive, to create, to surpass all the limits imposed on life and thought.  This is the cycle of critique, as it were, in which the active forces of life are captured by a negative will to power and become-reactive, but then, if they are taken to the limit of their negation, these reactive forces negate even themselves in a becoming-active.  We overcome the will to truth only by going under, by affirming precisely the will to power in the form of the will to self-preservation through self-deception, that led us to value truth to begin with.  

The activity of life is like a power of falsehood, of duping, dissimulating, dazzling and seducing. But, in order to be brought into effect, this power of falsehood must be selected, redoubled or repeated and thus elevated to a higher power. The power of falsehood must be taken as far as a will to deceive, an artistic will which alone is capable of competing with the ascetic ideal and successfully opposing it (NP, 102)

The fact that there is some sort of cycle here is why I've been placing 'opposite' in quotes.  In fact, the whole thrust of this chapter on critique has been to show us how the negative life self destructs and converts into a positive life that continues to transform and propagate.  When life is seen as positive and affirmative, there are no opposites.  Affirmation affirms even negation.  Becoming affirms even Being.  Thinking as art becomes a creative extension or re-doubling of the affirmative power of life, the power life has to make things up as it goes, to fabricate.  The very nature of an active life is to repeat itself as art, because the activity of life is only in its becoming-active.  

3.15

In the final subsection of the chapter, Deleuze contrasts two images of thought -- the "dogmatic" image that what thinking naturally wants is truth, and a new, but necessarily vague, image in which thought is whatever happens when we overcome the limits of our own stupidity.  The message is very similar to the third chapter of Difference & Repetition; we have to be forced to think by life, and the purpose of thinking is to envision new possibilities for living.  

The dogmatic image of thought is the one we usually take for granted.  That any thinking worthy of the name obviously wants truth above all else.  That this truth is to be found in a rational inquiry characteristic of humans alone.  And that, left to itself, that is, without the interference of irrational passions and politics, pure thinking alone will naturally reveal a single, objective, permanent truth.  We've already belabored the idea that the will to this kind of truth is a form of reactive nihilism.  What interests Deleuze here is the way that the dogmatic image of thought tries to silence any attempt to look behind it and enquire into the value of truth.  We haven't just forgotten to ask the question of truth's value, we have been actively discouraged from seeing it as a question.  

The most curious thing about this image of thought is the way in which it conceives of truth as an abstract universal. We are never referred to the real forces that form thought, thought itself is never related to the real forces that it presupposes as thought. Truth is never related to what it presupposes. But there is no truth that, before being a truth, is not the bringing into effect of a sense or the realisation of a value. Truth, as a concept, is entirely undetermined. Everything depends on the value and sense of what we think. We always have the truths we deserve as a function of the sense of what we conceive, of the value of what we believe. (NP, 103)

In other words, the dogmatic image of thought enshrines a completely empty type of thought. In D&R, Deleuze will say that it models thought on simple recognition of what's already there.  Why do we think?  How?  And under what circumstances?  These can't even become questions.  It's like suggesting that if you simply open your eyes, you'll see everything as it is.

Clearly, a new image of thought is opposed to the dogmatic image in every way.  If the dogmatic image is always of reactive thought, the new image asks what happens to thought when the one who thinks is active and affirmative.  To begin with, thought ceases to be about truth and becomes an affirmation of the power of falsehood, of creation, of fabrication.  

Conversely, our highest thoughts take falsehood into account; moreover, they never stop turning falsehood into a higher power, an affirmative and artistic power that is brought into effect, verified and becomes-true in the work of art.  (NP, 105)

But if thought does want truth, then its failure mode isn't error.  The worst thing that can happen to dogmatic thought is that it sees pink elephants instead of green ones.  By contrast, active thought isn't afraid of being 'wrong'.  When it fails it's because it doesn't do anything.  In this new image of thought the risk for thinking as such is that it never becomes-active, that it remains reactive.  This is what Deleuze calls "stupidity".   

Stupidity is a structure of thought as such: it is not a means of self-deception, it expresses the non-sense in thought by right. Stupidity is not error or a tissue of errors. There are imbecile thoughts, imbecile discourses, that are made up entirely of truths; but these truths are base, they are those of a base, heavy and leaden soul. The state of mind dominated by reactive forces, by right, expresses stupidity and, more profoundly, that which it is a symptom of: a base way of thinking. (NP, 105)

Philosophical thinking then becomes a way to combat stupidity by exposing the errors that limit our thought and prevent us from actively thinking, that keeps us reactive.  The dogmatic image of thought is a perfect example of stupidity.  It encapsulates a presumption of obviousness, and perhaps even a proof of the obvious by the obvious, all of which simply spins an elaborate web of intellectual deduction that prevents us from even thinking about the real problems of life.  Most of economics is stupid.  Because thinking is hard and hence rare.

The use of philosophy is to sadden. A philosophy that saddens no one, that annoys no one, is not a philosophy. It is useful for harming stupidity, for turning stupidity into something shameful. Its only use is the exposure of all forms of baseness of thought. Is there any discipline apart from philosophy that sets out to criticise all mystifications, whatever their source and aim, to expose all the fictions without which reactive forces would not prevail?  (NP, 106)

To avoid any confusion though, we should note that the stupidity Deleuze is referring to is always our own.  It's never someone else who is stupid.   We are the only ones who can be stupid, who can fail to think, who can stay within the limitations of our reactive life.  Which means that thinking is a task that constantly confronts us and which we can never have done with.  Every era has to do its own thinking because each time and place is defined by its own limits and the reflexive defense of its own status quo.    

Stupidity and baseness are always those of our own time, of our contemporaries, our stupidity and baseness.  Unlike the atemporal concept of error, baseness is inseparable from time, that is from this rapture of the present, from this present condition in which it is incarnated and in which it moves. This is why philosophy has an essential relation to time: it is always against its time, critique of the present world. The philosopher creates concepts that are neither eternal nor historical but untimely and not of the present. (NP, 107)

A second confusion is possible here if we don't understand the concept of stupidity in the context of the becoming-active of the will to power.  Though in a sense, it's a special case of the first confusion.  The critique of stupidity is a critique of our own stupidity -- our own culture's stupidity (and not how stupid they were "back then", "before we knew ..."), and our own personal stupidity (and not of those dummies who don't agree with us).  But who is it that carries out this critique?  In a sense, it's not even us.  Certainly, at least, it is not made by our essential self, our true nature, or our core interior identity.  Those are exactly the concepts we are criticizing!  It's easy to slip into seeing the overcoming of stupidity and the beginning of thinking as the romantic awakening of some powerful homunculus that previously lay dormant inside us.  But this myth is actually part of our stupidity, part of what separates us from our power of thought.  We don't think 'naturally'.  It is not an innate part of our being.  Forces can only become-active, and we can only become-thinkers.  Thus thinking is something that happens to thought, and only happens when we are forced to think, when something pushes our reactive patterns to their limit.  

Thinking, like activity, is always a second power of thought, not the natural exercise of a faculty, but an extraordinary event in thought itself, for thought itself. Thinking is the n-th power of thought. It is still necessary for it to become "light", "affirmative", "dancing". But it will never attain this power if forces do not do violence to it. Violence must be done to it as thought, a power, the force of thinking, must throw it into a becoming-active. (NP, 108)

The violence necessary for thinking, the self-destruction of the negative and stupidity, the merciless selective cultivation of the eternal return, are the final element of Deleuze's new image of thought.  Thought is dangerous stuff: "I am dynamite!".  It doesn't just recognize.  It creates.  And in the process of its birth, it necessarily destroys the illusions constitutive of our limited ego consciousness.  It's not we who think, but thought that happens to us, and through us, if we live affirmatively.  This is what Deleuze is saying when he talks about how thinking requires a culture.  Thought is not a product of the interiority of the lone individual, but the flower of a whole culture that merely appears through a solitary thinker.   Thus, thought must be cultured (like a bacteria) or cultivated (like a plant).  It requires cycle upon cycle of becoming-active, which is perhaps what Nietzsche means by "breeding".  It requires the whole genealogy we traced, even if only to overcome it.  The culture required for the new image of thought is directly opposed to the method that defined the dogmatic image.  Method restricts an infinite natural faculty and prevents it from accidentally falling into error, whereas culture culls away stupidity and enables the creation of something completely unnatural.    

Culture, according to Nietzsche, is essentially training and selection (UM III "Schopenhauer Educator" 6). It expresses the violence of the forces which seize thought in order to make it something affirmative and active.  We will only understand the concept of culture if we grasp all the ways in which it is opposed to method. Method always presupposes the good will of the thinker, "a premeditated decision". Culture, on the contrary, is a violence undergone by thought, a process of formation of thought through the action of selective forces, a training which brings the whole unconscious of the thinker into play. (NP, 108)

 Should we say that true thinking requires us to cultivate a path?

As a final post-script to this chapter, I can't resist pointing out one quote that seems to foreshadow the idea of the nomad war machine.  Culture may be a necessary condition for thought, but that doesn't mean it's sufficient.  The selective violence of culture can also be captured by those old representatives of the ascetic ideal -- the Church and the State.

The cultural work of active forces constantly risks being diverted from its course and sometimes it does benefit reactive forces. The Church or the State take on this violence of culture in order to realize their own ends. Reactive forces divert this violence from culture, turning it into a reactive force itself, a means of making even more stupid, of lowering thought. They confuse the violence of culture with their own violence, their own force (NP, 109)

This sounds a bit like the State Apparatus capturing the War Machine in A Thousand Plateaus.  It would take a lot of re-reading to lay out the details here, but I feel pretty confident that the War Machine finally getting nothing but war as its object (with fascism) is analogous to the moment where a negative will to power (WM) pushes a reactive force (SA) into a self-destructive becoming-active.  Thought is dangerous stuff indeed!

Thursday, January 5, 2023

Being Immanuel Kant

The first part of subsection 3.6 "Principles for the Philosophy of the Will" provides a succinct summary of how Nietzsche's theory of the will to power differs from prior theories of will and power.  Then it continues by setting the tone for the next 4 subsections (3.7-3.10) all of which deal in some way with the difference between Nietzschean and Kantian critique.  The theme holding all this together is an extension of the question we've been asking for a while now: who or which one critiques?  

"Who must undertake critique, who is fit to undertake it?" (NP, 88)

We already know the answer: at bottom, the will to power is always the one that ... (critiques, in this case).  We answer this way though, not because the will to power is some general transcendent principle that defines what the will wants in every empirical instance.  On the contrary, the will to power is what Deleuze keeps calling a "mobile, variable, plastic" principle.  What "power" means is actually defined by (and defines) the relations between forces that characterize any particular instance of the will (which, we recall, is just a force operating on another force).  It's almost like saying that power, as the 'principle' of the relation between forces, creates the will (which perhaps explains why Nietzsche can say in other places that, "there is no such thing as 'Will'").  There's no will that does not originate in and reflect a concrete hierarchy of power.  In this sense, the theory of the will to power is similar to what we usually call perspectivism, with the important caveat that in Nietzsche's theory, it's the perspective that creates the subject, rather than the pre-established subject that possesses one (or various) perspectives.  In the current context, this means that we must acknowledge up front that our critique in not universal, but comes from a particular perspective and embodies a particular will to power, namely, the one that constitutes our will.  The principle question then becomes what type of will does our critique express?

---------

Deleuze does a nice job summarizing his interpretation of the will to power on pages 84-85.  The key point is that willing is creative and joyous.  The will doesn't want to get a particular object that already exists.  Instead, as will to power, it fabricates that object as a valuable thing to want right now, at the same time that it fabricates itself as a willing subject with the power to possess that object.  In the will to power it is power that wills, that differentiates one force from another and creates a hierarchy or system of forces. 

Will to power does not imply any anthropomorphism in its origin, signification or essence. Will to power must be interpreted in a completely different way: power is the one that wills in the will. Power is the genetic and differential element in the will. This is why the will is essentially creative. (NP, 85)

Power is the ability to affect and be affected, to be connected to or capable of interacting with other stuff.  All power 'wants', all it does, is to go to the limit of this ability, to do everything it can do.  This limit is defined by the particular quality and relation of forces.  There's obviously something circular going on here.  Power produces a certain relation of forces where one attains an active quality and others react to it.  But then this relation of forces determines the quality of power (affirmative or negative) expressed by the hierarchy that was constructed.  Power seems to be expressed through a cycle involving the being of forces (active/reactive) and their becoming (affirmation and negation define a becoming-active or becoming-reactive).  

The genetic element (power) determines the relation of force with force and qualifies related forces. As plastic element it simultaneously determines and is determined, simultaneously qualifies and is qualified. What the will to power wills is a particular relation of forces, a particular quality of forces. And also a particular quality of power: affirming or denying. This complex, which varies in every case, forms a type to which given phenomena correspond. (NP, 85)

Power creates a will that wills to fully express this power.  This positive feedback loop can't be said to have any goal outside itself.  It operates, that is all.  Its operations define the signification of an object and the type of subject that values it.  Which is why Nietzsche will call it the "bestowing virtue" -- what bestows virtue.  

In this way the will to power is essentially creative and giving: it does not aspire, it does not seek, it does not desire, above all it does not desire power. It gives: power is something inexpressible in the will (something mobile, variable, plastic); power is in the will as "the bestowing virtue", through power the will itself bestows sense and value. (NP, 85)

--------

With this summary of the will to power in mind, we can move on and ask what type of will to power animates Nietzsche's own critique (and along the way analyze what type animates Kantian critique).  It will come as no shock that Deleuze discovers a negative will behind the Kantian critique and a positive and affirmative one behind Nietzsche's revaluation of the concept.  What's fascinating though is the implications this observation has for our understanding of the whole complex of concepts we've been discussing.  Nietzsche understands true critique as an affirmative becoming-active which, paradoxically, is only reached through the way the selective power of the eternal return causes the negative will to power to negate itself, and thus transmute into an affirmation of difference. Essentially, Deleuze is trying to bring the will to power, ER, and nihilism together into a neo-Kantian framework.  But this complex is treated in very compressed form, so it will take me a while to unpack it.  

Thus the typology of forces and the doctrine of the will to power are inseparable, in turn, from a critique which can be used to determine the genealogy of values, their nobility and baseness. - Of course one may ask in what sense and why noble is "worth more" than base or high "worth more" than low. By what right? There is no possible reply to this question if as we consider the will to power in itself or abstractly, as merely endowed with two opposite qualities, affirmation and negation. Why should affirmation be better than negation?  We will see that the solution can only be given by the test of the eternal return: what is better and better absolutely is that which returns, that which can bear returning, that which wills its return. (NP, 86)
 
We've mostly been discussing the will to power as a philosophical principle "in itself or abstractly".  But Nietzsche's whole point has been that behind every object there is a will to power that operates to produce both the sense and value of the object, as well as the signifying and valuing subject that corresponds to it.  And behind Nietzsche's philosophy is a concrete will to power that values affirmation over negation.  This will operates like an affirmation of affirmation.  In other words, it's a sort of self affirmation.  But what kind of self could be affirmed here?  It can't be our usual conscious, self-identical ego that defines itself as an interiority separated from everything exterior.  Nietzsche doesn't believe in the innate existence of this essential and atomic self, and we've seen how he considers its fabrication to be a product of reactive forces and the will to negation.  For a concrete will to power to affirm its self, it would actually need to affirm everything -- all the things that go into the hierarchy that define, and are defined by, this will to power.  In the simplest schematic example with one active and one reactive force, the affirmative will to power will need to affirm exactly that reactive force without which the active force cannot become what it is.  It doesn't affirm its identity, but the difference which distinguishes it from, but also holds it together with, its 'opposite'.  The affirmative self is a dissolved self, one that requires a medium in which it re-crystalizes.

But we've seen this whole structure before in exploring the way the eternal return cultivates (selects) through an affirmation so total that it affirms even negation.  And we've seen it before in the way that the the joyful is just the affirmation of the tragic.  Complete self affirmation must extend even to the affirmation of the 'other'.  Conversely, we've also seen that we only reach this active self-affirmation though a becoming-active that proceeded via the reactive force affirming its own power of negation.  This is the way the eternal return 'selects' the affirmative will to power.  If each concrete will to power wills itself, affirmative power ends up reinforcing itself, while negative power destroys itself.  Reactive forces, in affirming themselves and their own power of negation, end up negating themselves and transmuting themselves in a becoming active.  By contrast, active forces, in affirming themselves and their own power of affirmation, end up affirming their affinity with negation and the 'other' reactive forces.  Perhaps we can think of this affirmation of the 'opposite' either statically, as the affirmation of a necessary multi-layer hierarchy that includes the reactive, or dynamically, as an affirmation of the self-destruction of reactive forces required to become-active.  The basic message of ER is that affirmative will to power is self reinforcing; negative will to power is self defeating.

Negation limits itself, whereas affirmation increases without limit.  It sounds like we're discussing the difference between a positive or a negative feedback loop.  Normally, we think of either of these circuits as "self-reinforcing", and indeed, it's important to understand that either represents a will to power.  However, if we look more closely, we see the two types are not symmetrical.  A positive feedback loop doesn't reinforce it self so much as simply continue growing and expanding to infinity, engulfing everything it can.  A negative feedback loop, by contrast, doesn't actually reinforce itself so much as reinforces or preserves whatever equilibrium point it is set around.  In fact, a negative feedback loop tends to diminish itself and turn itself off.  In other words, a positive feedback loop genuinely reinforces itself, without needing to have any fixed concept of self; a negative feedback loop does not reinforce itself and is parasitic on some fixed concept of self that is external to its operation.  One might be tempted to object here that, surely, DNA replication constitutes a positive feedback loop of geometric growth.  Recalling the various critiques of Darwinism we've seen though, we might respond that life is actually the interaction of a positive and a negative feedback loop.  Does DNA really try to replicate its self, or does it merely spread or grow in space and time just lie a crystal does?  It's only the existence of an error correcting mechanism -- a negative feedback loop -- that introduces the concept of a self here at all.  I assert again that what's really positive and creative about life is the variation, not the replication.  This variation belongs to no one.

It may not be immediately obvious that this whole discussion is meant to answer the question of "who critiques?".  The affirmative will to power is the only true, complete, radical, and immanent critic.  And its critique operates through a self destruction of the negative within us.  In this sense, critique is always self critique, never the criticism of an other.  Finally, this critique is also joyful, in the sense that it increases our power, it removes our limits.  Its negation is in service of an active and creative will.  It tears down the fabrications and illusions that separate us from our power, it critiques these self imposed limits that made us become-reactive. Imagine Kant with a vajra.  

The eternal return transmutes the negative: it turns the heavy into something light, it makes the negative cross over to affirmation, it makes negation a power of affirming. But negation in this new form has become critique: destruction becomes active, aggression profoundly linked to affirmation. Critique is destruction as joy, the aggression of the creator. The creator of values cannot be distinguished from a destroyer, from a criminal or from a critic: a critic of established values, reactive values and baseness. (NP, 87)

--------

I think once we understand this connection between the concept of critique and the metaphysics of the will to power and eternal return we can easily understand the way the next three subsections contrast Nietzsche to Kant.  Subsection 3.7 simply observes that the inner logic of the plan of the Genealogy of Morals mirrors Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.  Having not read the latter I won't spend any time on this point.  Subsection 3.8 tells us that Kant's idea of critique merely intends to replace the content of one ideal with another.  He does nothing to critique the form of life that required an ideal to begin with.  Since all transcendent ideals are expressions of a negative will to power this means that Kant's notion of critique is still reactive.  He critiques pure reason only in an attempt to enshrine a perfected version of it.  He critiques our idea of God as a mystification, but then substitutes for it a mystic interiority of the subject that functions the same way.  It's a strange betrayal where Kant sets out to make a radical and total critique but arrives at the most conservative possible conclusions -- we should behave as if all our established ideas were true.  

If man is a reactive being what right has he to undertake a critique? Does the recuperation of religion stop us being religious? By turning theology into anthropology, by putting man in God's place, do we abolish the essential, that is to say, the place? All these ambiguities begin with the Kantian critique.  (NP, 88)

In subsection 3.9 we discover that Kant's notion of immanent critique was merely circular.  He wanted reason to critique itself, to discipline itself, to be the judge in its own trial.  But this requires some transcendent idea of what constitutes "reason", which of course we can only form through reason.  We need never leave the comfort of our established values.  By contrast, with his discovery of the will to power, Nietzsche is able to ask how reason is actually formed, and thus to ask whether what needs criticizing is not simply the particular contents but perhaps the whole form of reason.  

Trascendental principles are principles of conditioning and not of internal genesis. We require a genesis of reason itself, and also a genesis of the understanding and its categories: what are the forces of reason and of the understanding? What is the will which hides and expresses itself in reason? What stands behind reason, in reason itself? (NP, 91)

As we saw, understanding the connection between ER and the will to power provides for a truly immanent critique.  In becoming an active self-destruction of the negative concepts that limits us, Nietzschean critique transmutes our reactive forces into creative and "legislative" forces.  We don't critique in the name of some other pre-existing and transcendental value, but in the name of the freedom to impose a law on ourselves as we go -- the law of the Return.  The will to power's self-critique and the self destruction we saw it involved are at the same time a form of self creation.  As Zarathustra puts it, we don't go over without going under.  For Deleuze and Nietzsche, this immanent creation through critique is what defines philosophy and differentiates it from religion.  

It is not that the philosopher must add the activity of legislator to his other activities because he is in the best position to do this - as if his own subjection to wisdom qualified him to discover the best possible laws to which men in their turn ought to be subjected. The point is a completely different one: that the philosopher, as philosopher, is not a sage, that the philosopher, as philosopher, ceases to obey, that he replaces the old wisdom by command, that he destroys the old values and creates new ones, that the whole of his science is legislative in this sense. "Their 'knowing' is creating, their creating is a law-giving, their will to truth is - will to power" (BGE 211). (P, 92)

Finally, subsection 3.10 is a summary of the contrast between Nietzsche and Kant.  I think we've covered most of these points, but two of them stand out.  First, critique is creative, and what it creates is the Overhuman.  If we've been following along, we now can't confuse this concept with some concrete new ideal or goal for individual human beings.  The overhuman is a completely different form of the human -- precisely the form that went under itself through critique, and thereby transmuted all the negative and reactive aspects of its previous ideals.  

The aim of critique is not the ends of man or of reason but in the end the Overman, the overcome, overtaken man. The point of critique is not justification but a different way of feeling: another sensibility. (NP, 94)

Second, there's an interesting point here about about what Nietzsche means by "irrationalism".  We're criticizing reason in the name of the will to power.  Clearly, in some sense this will is 'irrational', since it lies outside of reason.  Does this that Nietzsche criticizes reason from the perspective of a romantic, that is, on the basis of some sort of feeling or passion?  Deleuze answers that no, this is a critique of reasonable thought by some other type of thought.  Reason does not have a monopoly on thought that can only be opposed by some other faculty like feeling or sensing.  Nietzsche's critique of reason is still from within thought.

It is a serious mistake to think that irrationalism opposes anything but thought to reason - whether it be the rights of the given, of the heart, of feeling, caprice or passion. In irrationalism we are concerned only with thought, only with thinking. What is opposed to reason is thought itself; what is opposed to the reasonable being is the thinker himself. Because it is reason which receives and expresses the rights of that which dominates thought, thought reconquers its rights and becomes a legislator against reason: the dicethrow, this was the sense of the dicethrow. (NP, 93)
 
This brings up an obvious question.  What does this other 'irrational' kind of thought look like?  How does our thinking work when it is not dominated by the limits of reason?  That's really the question for the rest of this chapter.