Friday, May 29, 2020

Eternally Returning

Deleuze always comes back to the eternal return as the high point of his attempt to think of difference in-itself as repetition for-itself.  As befits the content of the concept, each time is appears it has a slightly different form.  This time, the emphasis is on it's relationship to possibility and to a pure chance the removes all traces of the concept of necessity.  Eternal return is linked to the death instinct, but the death it implies liberates a sense of play and invention.  As Nozick put it in Invariances: "only lack of invention is the mother of necessity".

At first sight it's not obvious that the ER would be opposed to the idea of necessity.  On the contrary, if we understand it as the proposition that at some point everything will repeat again in identical fashion, it seems to suggest that absolutely everything necessarily must be just as it is and was, as if it were all part of God's inscrutable plan for the universe. [Note: I am going to use "world" and universe" synonymously here]  After all, this is not even the first time it's all happening, right?  However, no philosopher has ever worked as hard to be misunderstood as Nietzsche, and ER has to be his most misunderstood concept.  In fact, the idea is meant to lead us in exactly the opposite direction of a fixed and necessary repetition by forcing us to ask some questions about how that would work.  It takes quite a bit of work to see this reversed perspective though.

You ask yourself, for example: when did the latest cycle of the universe start?  Obviously, the answer is: after the last one ended.  So, maybe when time ends, it repeats again from the beginning.  The form of time and its contents would both be both finite and repeating.  Or maybe, rather than starting again, we might instead conceive of time as progressing in an infinite straight line.  Since matter and space are finite though, if things keep moving around long enough they will inevitably end up back in the starting position (at least that's the intuition, I rather liked George Simmel's counter-example here).  In that case the form of time would be infinite, but its contents are finite and repeating (which when you think about it kinda defeats the idea of its form being infinite, see below). These are two not actually very different flavors of how the universe could repeat itself.   

Given our ideas about the big bang and the heat death of the universe, they may sound plausible to the modern ear.  We might wonder whether it repeats again exactly, with the exact same initial conditions at the Big Bang leading, via the inexorable laws of physics, to the exact same evolution of the universe, right down to me typing this exact same sentence with it's reference to G-Eazy, followed immediately by zombie apocalypse and heat death.  But, regardless of whether we start with the same initial conditions every time or whether we try to argue that ER is wrong and no two universes are alike because of tiny random variation in the initial conditions, the basic idea seems to make conceptual sense -- 'everything' could repeat.

It make sense to us because we are so accustomed to the basic assumptions of a materialist worldview.  We situate ourselves outside of the world, looking at it from above as a closed totality with beginning and end, governed by specifiable laws that are also outside that world.  What's repeated empirically (or not) would be the universe as a whole.   And what's repeated transcendentally, as a condition necessary for thinking about the first repetition, are the identity of the immaterial laws that govern it.  It's only from this viewpoint outside the material world that we can stand back and see what counts as a full cycle and count the number of times it has repeated.  This is the perspective that gives time a hinge that divides one repetition from the next.  This is the only perspective from which we can imagine running the experiment of the universe a second time.

That all seems like a perfectly coherent perspective till I write it down.  I mean that literally.  Because as I write it down, I somehow appropriate that external perspective for myself.  Yet, the last time I checked, I was still just a hairless chimp floating through space on an unremarkable rock, seemingly as much a part of the universe as anything else.  So how did I, or any part within this universe, manage to attain the perspective of looking at it from without, the only perspective that would enable me to see whether or not it repeats?  

Or maybe more succinctly, we might ask: how did I write this whole blog post down the first time?  After all, the first spin of the merry-go-round was not a repetition.  The unit of repetition had yet to be formed.  So of course that time I was not busy writing about how it repeats, because it hadn't yet.  But, well, I'm writing this and you're reading it, so either this is indeed the first time, or this time is somehow different from it precisely because I'm here identifying the repetition.  In either case, my thought that the universe repeats is true it would count as evidence that it does not repeat.  

Or maybe we think there was no first time, and the unit of repetition has simply always been there.  I've always sat here writing this exact same line, and you've always sat here reading it.  But then, how would we know?  How would we ever figure out which number repetition we're in?  We would have to have some memory of the last time around with which to confirm the identity, but like we saw with Hume, this would add a privileged point or extra dimension to the experience that makes each time around different.  But if this unit is simply all there ever is over and over again, and there is no overlap or static supplementary dimension, doesn't the whole idea of a repetition lose all meaning?  

It kinda reminds me of the sophomoric notion of base reality.  Sure, maybe we're in a simulation instead of base reality.  But then again maybe it's just a simulation of a simulation.  Or etc ... And how would you know the difference between base reality and a simulation, or one simulation and another, unless you find some way of passing from one to the next?  And even if Elon Musk perfects astral travel before he gulps another red pill, how would one level announce itself as more real or base than any other?  The act of considering possible simulations renders the concept of base reality meaningless.  

The point with all this analytic rambling is that if there's someone who can think this thought or write this very sentence, then the idea that the universe repeats exactly becomes internally incoherent.  There's a non-obvious paradox built into the eternal return, a self-referential structure perhaps a bit like the diagonal method or Gödel's proof.  This is why it comes up again here in the context of the death instinct, which for Deleuze is associated with a dissolving self-referential process

As Klossowski says, it is the secret coherence which establishes itself only by excluding my own coherence, my own identity, the identity of the self, the world and God.

But just when you thought this had gotten dizzying enough, you can see in this quote the glimmer of yet another twist.  The expression of the idea that the history of the world is a unit that necessarily repeats seems to dissolve that very idea.   The natural contrary would seem to be that the world must only unfold one time, once and for all, as a completely unique entity.  Except, part of that universe is busy imagining that the universe, and it itself, repeats.  You might say that this is just some sort of hallucination.  This is the simplest refutation of what I wrote above -- the idea that the universe repeats just isn't true.  But now your base reality must contain perfectly real hallucinations, objective illusions.  These hallucinations actually work just like little simulated thought images of our whole universe, except with the added difference that in those simulations it is all happening again the same way.  But of course that makes it different from the perspective of the thinker of the simulation, who has to hold reality and the simulation together to image their relationship as one of repetition.  So if we have just one universe in which the question of the eternal return has been asked, it suddenly fragments into miniature copies of itself, each of which is actually a different repetition of the whole, within that whole, ad infinitum.  Even if that question is an illusion or a hallucination, it still produces this fragmentation as real effect, and in fact, our only approach to this whole is through these hallucinations that are now objectively part of it.

The world is neither finite nor infinite as representation would have it: it is completed and unlimited. Eternal return is the unlimited of the finished itself, the univocal being which is said of difference. 

It's difficult to talk about the eternal return because it has this strange circulation built directly into the idea.  Paradox in general has this sort of effect.  "This statement is false".  If it is, it isn't, and if it isn't, it is.  There's an internal movement or restlessness.  With a simple paradox that doesn't get you anywhere because you just move in a circle.  But with ER, you get back a new world every time, but in the form of the possibilities that were already inherent in this one.  If I think that the world repeats then it must not, but if it doesn't then my thought that it does creates a repetition that didn't exist before, and then this cycle repeats, splitting into new worlds again and again.  The thought of a unique world repeating is the thought of an infinite multiplicity of different worlds.

When we asked who annihilates themself with the death instinct, we discovered that the unbound energy produced by the third synthesis actually provided the fuel for the first synthesis.  The universal unconscious appeared as the remains of a multitude of dissolved consciousnesses that had reached a high point of self-annihilation.  Similarly, ER can't become incoherent and dissolve the idea of repetition without taking the thinker and the whole world along with it.  It's a thought that dissolves all the forms of identity, including its own.  God, self, and world -- natural law, conceptualizer of that law, and universe -- all dissolve together.

The eternal return is a force of affirmation, but it affirms everything of the multiple, everything of the different, everything of chance except what subordinates them to the One, to the Same, to necessity, everything except the One, the Same and the Necessary.  It is said that the One subjugated the multiple once and for all. But is this not the face of death? And does not the other face cause to die in turn, once and for all, everything which operates once and for all?  If there is an essential relation between eternal return and death, it is because it promises and implies 'once and for all' the death of that which is one.  If there is an essential relation with the future, it is because the future is the deployment and explication of the multiple, of the different and of the fortuitous, for themselves and 'for all times'.

It's brain-busting to try and conceive of the "completed but unlimited" fractal world that the eternal return implies.  Nested within 'the' world are an infinite number of other worlds, and nested within those are ... 'The' world is this monstrous and completely unique infinite totality that nevertheless repeats itself internally.  The crazy structure is necessitated by thinking about the world as a whole, including about how you could possibly be thinking about it as a whole.  The only thing that is not present in this infinite unfurling is any stopping point, any natural unity, or pre-established harmony, or fixed set of laws that remain outside it.  It's everything -- a cosmos as chaos, where anything can happen because everything does happen.  

We began our exploration of whether the universe repeats by separating the question into the application of a fixed set of external laws to some initial condition.  The laws were presumed to always be the same, but the condition might (or might not) be chosen randomly every time we run the experiment of the world, so to speak.  This gave the world a single fixed probability distribution of possible outcomes once and for all.  But chimp science seems to pose an insoluble metaphysical problem for this way of looking at the world.  Instead, we're forced to imagine a unique world where the laws themselves change with each 'repetition', as if there were another stage of randomness in which certain laws were chosen, and from there an initial condition selected.  But this goes on ad infinitum, because what distribution of possible laws were the particular laws selected from?  Etc ...  What we end up trying to conceive is a sort of total chance, chance multiplied by itself again and again, raised to a higher power.  Hopefully this thought illuminates Deleuze's reflections on the infinite game that the eternal return represents.

It is claimed that man does not know how to play: this is because, even when he is given a situation of chance or multiplicity, he understands his affirmations as destined to impose limits upon it, his decisions as destined to ward off its effects, his reproductions as destined to bring about the return of the same, given a winning hypothesis. This is precisely a losing game, one in which we risk losing as much as winning because we do not affirm the all of chance: the pre-established character of the rule which fragments has as its correlate the condition by default in the player, who never knows which fragment will emerge. The system of the future, by contrast, must be called a divine game, since there is no pre-existing rule, since the game bears already upon its own rules and since the child-player can only win, all of chance being affirmed each time and for all times. Not restrictive or limiting affirmations, but affirmations coextensive with the questions posed and with the decisions from which these emanate: such a game entails the repetition of the necessarily winning move, since it wins by embracing all possible combinations and rules in the system of its own return.

Finally, Deleuze is right that absolutely no one has done better than Borges in imagining this dizzying world of total chance.  I won't re-quote the Borges on pg. 116 here because we ought to just re-read the two stories that the quote mashes up.  The Lottery of Babylon, and The Garden of the Forking Paths.




Monday, May 25, 2020

Whose?

Deleuze dedicates the last couple pages of the section ending on pg. 115 to summarizing the third synthesis and the way it relates to the other two.  I won't spend a ton of time here because we've seen all this before in much greater detail.  Continuing the theme of the last post, I feel like the main question lurking behind these pages is what agent we could be talking about once we reach the point of dissolution of identity implicit in the third synthesis.  Deleuze highlights the issue by italicizing the "of" in his summary of the components of the third synthesis.

It is all in the same movement that there is a reflux of Eros on to the ego, that the ego takes upon itself the disguises and displacements which characterise the objects in order to construct its own fatal affection, that the libido loses all mnemic content and Time loses its circular shape in order to assume a merciless and straight form, and that the death instinct appears, indistinguishable from that pure form, the desexualised energy of that narcissistic libido.

The narcissistic ego discovers that it itself is the ultimate erotic virtual object continually displaced onto and disguised within the world.  It was never a lost memory, even a mythical one, that it was searching for.  It was always only its self, namely the process of the formation of those memories through an endless displacement and disguise, without any original content.  As a result there is nothing to circle back to but this process of unfolding, no object of the ego except itself taking itself taking itself ... as object.   When the ego realizes itself as this infinitely splitting line, the object loses all its mysterious erotic pull and becomes desexualized.  The sexual energy that was invested in it is freed, unbound from the ego which has dissolved itself along with its object.  

But wait?  So now whose energy is it?  Who died?  And if this is the moment where the activity of the ego become thought, then whose thought is it?  How can it be the energy "of" the narcissistic libido if this is precisely what's dissolving?  Our normal idea of ownership, of a subject that owns some properties, is going haywire here, as if we carried our compass to the North Pole.  The desexualized energy is only produced by the narcissistic libido, and yet that ego consumes itself in the process of the production.  So what are we left with afterwards?

I think that Deleuze's answer is basically that we are left almost where we began, with the unconscious.  Not my unconscious or your unconscious though, but the unconscious, its unconscious.  Remember how we began our discussion of psychoanalysis:

Biopsychical life implies a field of individuation in which differences in intensity are distributed here and there in the form of excitations. The quantitative and qualitative process of the resolution of such differences is what we call pleasure. A totality of this kind - a mobile distribution of differences and local resolutions within an intensive field - corresponds to what Freud called the Id, or at least the primary layer of the Id. The word 'id' in this sense is not only a pronoun referring to some formidable unknown, but also an adverb referring to a mobile place, a 'here and there' of excitations and resolutions. 

This primary layer of the id was quickly bound and organized by habit in the first synthesis.  But we have returned to this field of difference where excitations are unbound from any form.  

It is these three syntheses which must be understood as constitutive of the unconscious. 

In other words, the unconscious has become an agent.  "It" is the answer to all our questions (or perhaps more accurately the source of them).  The liberated energy 'belongs' to the unconscious.  We are a local excitation and resolution within that impersonal field.  And thinking is the energy that discharges through it like a lightning strike, drawing an abstract line that encloses no form.  Thinking arises from within this unconscious, and returns to it.  Thought, "distinguishes itself -- and yet that from which it distinguishes itself does not distinguish itself from it".  

I believe this is what Deleuze is trying to get across with his reference to Artaud here.  

... it is no longer a question of knowing whether thought is innate or acquired. It is neither innate nor acquired but genital -- in other words, desexualised and drawn from that reflux which opens us on to empty time. In order to indicate this genesis of thought in an always fractured I, Artaud said: 'I am an innate genital', meaning equally thereby a 'desexualised acquisition'. It is not a question of acquiring thought, nor of exercising it as though it were innate, but of engendering the act of thinking within thought itself.

This gets only slightly clearer when Deleuze quotes Artaud more fully on pg. 148:

To think is to create -- there is no other creation -- but to create is first of all to engender 'thinking' in thought. For this reason Artaud opposes genitality to innateness in thought, but equally to reminiscence, and thereby proposes the principle of a transcendental empiricism: 
I am innately genital. ... There are some fools who think of themselves as beings, as innately being. I am he who, in order to be, must whip his innateness. One who innately must be a being, that is always whipping this sort of non-existent kennel, 0 bitches of impossibility! ... Underneath grammar there lies thought, an infamy harder to conquer, an infinitely more shrewdish maid, rougher to overcome when taken as an innate fact. For thought is a matron who has not always existed.

Thinking doesn't belong to us innately.  It's the unconscious that thinks through us, as it were.  Yet we don't acquire thought from somewhere else as a new property for ourselves either.  It's more like thinker and thought are produced together.  In other words, we are a necessary vehicle for thought.  Not that I in particular, or the human species in general, is a necessary vehicle.  But some vehicle, some thinker, some agent or conceptual personae (as D&G put it in What is Philosophy?) is necessary.  This thinker must be whipped into existence from the "bitches of impossibility" as simultaneously necessary and utterly disposable, destined to erase itself with one hand as it draws itself with the other.   

Now though we've ended up in a very strange place.  Because not only has the thinker dissolved but so has the unconscious.  We began with the unbound excitations of an unconscious field, subject here and there to spontaneous resolution.  But we've discovered that this energy is only produced as liberated from the dissolution of the ego we called thinking.  It's unclear what's the given and what's the endpoint.  "The" unconscious we were talking about doesn't pre-exist as some sort of original totality.  The third synthesis produces the unbound and ungrounded starting point for the first.  

At this extreme point the straight line of time forms a circle again, a singularly tortuous one; or alternatively, the death instinct reveals an unconditional truth hidden in its 'other' face - namely, the eternal return in so far as this does not cause everything to come back but, on the contrary, affects a world which has rid itself of the default of the condition and the equality of the agent in order to affirm only the excessive and the unequal, the interminable and the incessant, the formless as the product of the most extreme formality.

It's as if the lightning strike of thought turned out to be the background radiation of the universe.  As if the once and for all split of time into before and after that characterized the third synthesis turned out to be every moment.  And we already know that to live every moment as if it were once and for all is the whole point of the enteral return.  

Saturday, May 23, 2020

How can I die if there is no me to begin with?

I take that to be the shortened rhetorical version of the two aspects of death that Deleuze identifies in Blanchot on pg. 112 and 113.  We actually stumbled across this question way back in the introduction when we wondered why repetition was somehow related to death and terror.  Death is always going to be a question of identity.  Who dies?  Which begs the question: who am I?  At this point, we now have an entire framework for thinking about how our identity might arise as a second principle, through a repetition of difference.  Which is to say that we are no longer taking our identity for granted at the outset.  Hence the questions.  If my identity is produced through a process of repetition -- a process that we've seen is structurally equivalent to the unfolding of time, its cleaving into the qualitative difference of before and after (the process, you might say) -- then what is lost when this identity disappears?

Deleuze points out that the answer to this question depends on what we mean by identity.  If we mean my particular identity as a personal I or ego, then of course everything is lost in death.  It is the negation of my existence.  If, however, we mean my 'identity' as that repeated process of unfolding, well ... then there is no I to die.  Nothing can be lost because there is nothing to lose.  Or we might equivalently say that I am dying all the time. Though the I that is dying here is not a particular identity but a process that produces a whole series of identities.   Death is the symbol of precisely this process, or rather, the paradoxical way that this process can take itself as an object or 'identity', and hence repeat the empty form of time.  All that is lost in this sense of death is the first form of identity.  

Thus there are two types of death, which correspond to two ways of identifying ourself.

The first signifies the personal disappearance of the person, the annihilation of this difference represented by the I or the ego. This is a difference which existed only in order to die, and the disappearance of which can be objectively represented by a return to inanimate matter, as though calculated by a kind of entropy

The other death, however, the other face or aspect of death, refers to the state of free differences when they are no longer subject to the form imposed upon them by an I or an ego, when they assume a shape which excludes my own coherence no less than that of any identity whatsoever. There is always a 'one dies' more profound than 'I die', and it is not only the gods who die endlessly and in a variety of ways; as though there appeared worlds in which the individual was no longer imprisoned within the personal form of the I and the ego, nor the singular imprisoned within the limits of the individual - in short, the insubordinate multiple, which cannot be 'recognised' in the first aspect.

We can see in this quote anther concept that reminds me of another connection made in the introduction that it seems we never discussed.  Death is related to liberation, to freedom.

If repetition makes us ill, it also heals us; if it enchains and destroys us, it also frees us, testifying in both cases to its 'demonic' power. 

How can this game be related to the death instinct? No doubt in a sense close to that in which Miller, in his wonderful book on Rimbaud, says: 'I realized that I was free, that the death I had gone through had liberated me.'

What we are freed from in the second version of death is the imprisoning limits of our particular identity.  And we are freed to experience the multiple as the power a singularity (like death) has to repeat itself.  A singularity that has a type of (non)-being or ?-being that repeats, and that contains a multiplicity within itself, is the central paradox of Deleuze's idea of repetition.  

To repeat is to behave in a certain manner, but in relation to something unique or singular which has no equal or equivalent. And perhaps this· repetition at the level of external conduct echoes, for its own part, a more secret vibration which animates it, a more profound, internal repetition within the singular. This is the apparent paradox of festivals: they repeat an 'unrepeatable'. They do not add a second and a third time to the first, but carry the first time to the 'nth' power. 

I can't leave this topic without mentioning that the second conception of death seems to me as good an explanation of Nirvana as any I have heard.  A "blowing out" or a "quenching".  A "cessation" that liberates one from a cycle of desiring.  An idea at least closely related to non-self (maybe the same thing).  In other words, an ending that keeps on happening.  Somehow  at once singular and related to time and change, as if it were frozen but vibrating internally.  We could multiply analogies here, but I'm not sure it would help convince any skeptic of their striking connection; one could always wonder whether all paradoxical things are ultimately the same. 

What's more interesting to me than trying to convince anyone of the merits of the comparison is the way Deleuze's description can perhaps guide my meditation practice.  He provides a whole mechanism for how the 'nirvana instinct' arises, the key piece of which seems to be the way the self folds back on itself and takes itself as the perpetually displaced virtual object that circulates through all our desires.  Somehow this circularity is meant to dissolve us and liberate us at the same time, as if we become identified with the question, "who am I?" rather than identifying ourself with any of the answers.


Wednesday, May 20, 2020

The Synthesis of Death 2

Last time we tried to get a handle on the way the third synthesis was related to the other two.  To recapitulate the recapitulation ...

There was a first synthesis of form, where difference was produced by a habitual repetition as something external to it.  There was a second synthesis of process, where different forms were included within a repeating process that pre-existed them.  Finally, we reached a third synthesis that considered the whole process of the second synthesis as a form in itself.  We can think of this as reflecting the second synthesis back on itself or as synthesizing the first two syntheses together.  With the third synthesis we reach the point where process and form have become 'identical' and the only thing repeating is differentiation itself.  This is basically Deleuze's definition of time -- the empty form of qualitative change from before to after -- "time is the most radical form of change, but the form of change does not change".

We did not get as far as connecting this to Freud's idea of the death drive and its relationship to the super-ego, because I foresaw that it would require an extended detour into The Ego and the Id to fully appreciate what Deleuze is up to here.  

Aside from that connection, the basic idea is fairly simple.  Death is the symbol of time.  It involves a before and after separated and yet joined by a moment of qualitative change.  It is, famously, the one constant of life (I no longer pay my taxes).  Death, time itself, the continual process of qualitative transformation -- which is to say difference -- is the only thing that's repeated identically.      

When the narcissistic ego takes the place of the virtual and real objects, when it assumes the displacement of the former and the disguise of the latter, it does not replace one content of time with another. On the contrary, we enter into the third synthesis. It is as though time had abandoned all possible mnemic content, and in so doing had broken the circle into which it was lead by Eros. It is as though it had unrolled, straightened itself and assumed the ultimate shape of the labyrinth, the straight-line labyrinth which is, as Borges says, 'invisible, incessant'. Time empty and out of joint, with its rigorous formal and static order, its crushing unity and its irreversible series, is precisely the death instinct.

[Incidentally, the reference to Borges' Death and The Compass provides a beautiful image of the third synthesis -- Zeno's infinitely splitting line:

"In your labyrinth there are three lines too many," he said at last. "I know of a Greek labyrinth which is a single straight line. Along this line so many philosophers have lost themselves that a mere detective might well do so too. Scharlach, when, in some other incarnation you hunt me, feign to commit (or do commit) a crime at A, then a second crime at B, eight kilometers from A, then a third crime at C, four kilometers from A and B, halfway enroute between the two. Wait for me later at D, two kilometers from A and C, halfway, once again, between both. Kill me at D, as you are now going to kill me at Triste-le-Roy." 
 
"The next time I kill you," said Scharlach, "I promise you the labyrinth made of the single straight line which is invisible and everlasting." 
 
He stepped back a few paces. Then, very carefully, he fired.

--------

So now let's go back and enrich this abstract definition of time as death by relating it to Freud's ideas.  To understand how Deleuze's version of the death instinct plays off of Freud, we need to cover Freud's dualistic theory of drives, as well as his three part theory of the psyche. 

We already talked a little about Freud's idea of the instincts when we asked whether consciousness was just the opposite of the unconscious.  All instincts, for Freud, have a "regressive" character in the sense that they seek to repeat an earlier state of things; that's in fact why we call them instincts, because they come to us a ready made drives to do X, again, just like our ancestors did.  But these instincts come in two dualistically opposed flavors.  The life instincts (Eros) seek to bind things together.  Freud somewhat bizarrely suggests this may be a desire to repeat an ancient state of mythical unity like the description of a hermaphroditic garden of Eden that Plato puts into the mouth of Aristophanes at the end of the Symposium.   The death instinct seeks to take things apart.  It is the drive that all organic life has to return to its objective original inorganic (ie. dead) state.  Here's how Freud himself (writing in The Ego and the Id) summarizes the thesis of Beyond the Pleasure Principle:

I have lately developed a view of the instincts which I shall here hold to and take as the basis of my further discussions. According to this view we have to distinguish two classes of instincts, one of which, the sexual instincts or Eros, is by far the more conspicuous and accessible to study. It comprises not merely the uninhibited sexual instinct proper and the instinctual impulses of an aim inhibited or sublimated nature derived from it, but also the self-preservative instinct, which must be assigned to the ego and which at the beginning of our analytic work we had good reason for contrasting with the sexual object-instincts. The second class of instincts was not so easy to point to; in the end we came to recognize sadism as its representative. On the basis of theoretical considerations, supported by biology, we put forward the hypothesis of a death instinct, the task of which is to lead organic life back into the inanimate state; on the other hand, we supposed that Eros, by bringing about a more and more far-reaching combination of the particles into which living substance is dispersed, aims at complicating life and at the same time, of course, at preserving it. Acting in this way, both the instincts would be conservative in the strictest sense of the word, since both would be endeavouring to re-establish a state of things that was disturbed by the emergence of life. The emergence of life would thus be the cause of the continuance of life and also at the same time of the striving towards death; and life itself would be a conflict and compromise between these two trends. The problem of the origin of life would remain a cosmological one; and the problem of the goal and purpose of life would be answered dualistically

Deleuze follows Freud in thinking of instincts -- passions, things that happen to us and come from outside us -- as related to repetition.  However, Deleuze rejects both the dualistic theory of instincts, as well as the theory of repetition associated with it.  As you can see from the quote above, repetition for Freud is either the repetition of some objective first state of things, or some ancient mythical state of things.  Both of these repetitions are measured by the logic of counting the number of copies of a self-identical model.  When repetition is subordinated to a model like this, it also immediately subjugates difference to an opposition between the reality of the model and the appearance of the copy.  In Freud's case this means that the unconscious becomes a battleground between the drive of Thanatos to restore an original state of equilibrium (aka. death), and the non-equilibrium perturbations of Eros that oppose and cover over that initial state.  Deleuze doesn't believe in a conflict between the instincts because this reduces their difference to opposition of negation, difference between, and fails to give us difference-in-itself.  And he doesn't believe that the "passion for repetition" they make evident is a drive to repeat some objective model, because this wouldn't give us repetition-for-itself, but repetition of something.

But does Deleuze offer a theory of instincts of his own?  In fact, we might think of each of the passive syntheses as a type of instinct that has a particular type of repetition that corresponds to it. 1) Habitus and the repetition of form as bound difference -- a habitual instinct 2) Eros-Mnemosyne and the repetition of process -- our intertwined sexual and self-preservative instincts 3) Thanatos and the repetition of the empty form of repetition -- a death instinct.  

Alternatively, we could look at each of these syntheses as developments of a single unconscious 'instinct' (scare quotes to indicate that this instinct is related to a repetition that never had a first time, and has no goal).  Each synthesis would then correspond to a newly differentiated layer of the psychic structure.  Together, they describe the way the unconscious differentiates itself into the Id, the Ego, and the Super-Ego just like an embryo differentiates itself into a full blown organism.  

It is these three syntheses which must be understood as constitutive of the unconscious.

But to understand this perspective, and to connect it to the death instinct, we need to back up a bit and review how Freud arrived at his three part structure.

We've encountered some of Freud's ideas about the id and the ego already.  Psychoanalysis, with its hypothesis of unconscious desires, takes the unknown id as its starting point.  This doesn't mean that the id in itself has no structure or is some amorphous matter.  In fact, we already saw in Beyond the Pleasure Principle that excitations in the id could be bound or unbound.  Freud thought that the ego is responsible for this binding, which seemed essentially to amount to a blocking or channeling of a flow of 'psychic fluid' so to speak, by a surface.  The little Freud I've read does not make it completely clear how this surface ego first appears on the scene.  Since the analogy is to a cell membrane, maybe he thinks of it it from an almost anatomical evolutionary perspective, as something that must be around if we are to separate inside from outside, my id from yours, and have an organism to begin with.  Or maybe the causality implied in question is less important than it seems -- the Id differentiates itself into a surface level, and then this new functional level appears to react back upon the id.   However it arises, it's clear that Freud considers the ego a surface differentiation of the id, and he relates it to the perceptual-motor system that governs the interactions between our inner drives and the outer world.  Once it forms to interface with the external world, the ego also becomes capable of binding excitations that come from within the organism, and repurposing them for its own use.  This binding organizes the unruly flow of the id by making the pursuit of pleasure the principle of its operation.  Synthesis #1.

The part we have yet to discuss is the organization of the ego itself.  In The Ego and the Id, Freud outlines his theory of how the ego further differentiates itself into another layer: the ego-Ideal or super-ego.  The key to this theory turns out to be his idea of "secondary narcissism".  It's not that the ego loves itself directly, it's that at a certain point in its development, it substitutes itself in place of a sexual object that the id has been forced to give up.

When it happens that a person has to give up a sexual object, there quite often ensues an alteration of his ego which can only be described as a setting up of the object inside the ego, as it occurs in melancholia; the exact nature of this substitution is as yet unknown to us. It may be that by this introjection, which is a kind of regression to the mechanism of the oral phase, the ego makes it easier for the object to be given up or renders that process possible. It may be that this identification is the sole condition under which the id can give up its objects. At any rate the process, especially in the early phases of development, is a very frequent one, and it makes it possible to suppose that the character of the ego is a precipitate of abandoned object-cathexes and that it contains the history of those object-choices.

... this transformation of an erotic object-choice into an alteration of the ego is also a method by which the ego can obtain control over the id and deepen its relations with it—at the cost, it is true, of acquiescing to a large extent in the id's experiences. When the ego assumes the features of the object, it is forcing itself, so to speak, upon the id as a love-object and is trying to make good the id's loss by saying: 'Look, you can love me too—I am so like the object.' 

This would seem to imply an important amplification of the theory of narcissism. At the very beginning, all the libido is accumulated in the id, while the ego is still in process of formation or is still feeble. The id sends part of this libido out into erotic object-cathexes, whereupon the ego, now grown stronger, tries to get hold of this object-libido and to force itself on the id as a love-object. The narcissism of the ego is thus a secondary one, which has been withdrawn from objects.

It's as if the surface ego becomes a projective screen -- when the id looks out, all it sees is the ego in place of its former objects.  From the point of view of that ego though, this implies a sort of division or differentiation where it ends up positing itself as outside itself, so to speak.  On the one hand the ego is meant to control and direct the id, to channel its desires.  But on the other hand this controller now itself becomes an object of desire.  There's some sort of process of reflection implied here that's difficult to describe.  Perhaps we can imagine the ego acquiring two layers composed of one-way mirrors -- an inner one that reflects the world but let's the excitations of the id pass through, and an outer one that allows the world in while reflecting back the desires of the id (functioning as projective screen).  The ego is then formed by being trapped between these two mirrors.  Synthesis #2.

What is created by this modification of differentiation of the ego is the super-ego.  Freud's full explanation of this is complex.  However, I don't think we need to go into it deeply to understand Deleuze.  The simple summary would be that as male (everyone is male for Freud) children we sexually desire our mothers and identify with our fathers (the Oedipus Complex).  At some point though, reality sets in and we realize that we are never going to lay mom because dad stands in the way.  Cock-blocked, our ego responds by offering itself in place of mom, meaning that we've also now produced a narcissistic identification with our mother.  This resolves the external Oedipus complex because we've given up the mother as a sexual object, but at the price of introducing a new structural modification in the ego.

The broad general outcome of the sexual phase dominated by the Oedipus complex may, therefore, be taken to be the forming of a precipitate in the ego, consisting of these two identifications in some way united with each other. This modification of the ego retains its special position; it confronts the other contents of the ego as an ego ideal or super-ego. 
 
The super-ego is, however, not simply a residue of the earliest object choices of the id; it also represents an energetic reaction-formation against those choices. Its relation to the ego is not exhausted by the precept: 'You ought to be like this (like your father).' It also comprises the prohibition: 'You may not be like this (like your father)—that is, you may not do all that he does; some things are his prerogative.' This double aspect of the ego ideal derives from the fact that the ego ideal had the task of repressing the Oedipus complex; indeed, it is to that revolutionary event that it owes its existence. Clearly the repression of the Oedipus complex was no easy task. The child's parents, and especially his father, were perceived as the obstacle to a realization of his Oedipus wishes; so his infantile ego fortified itself for the carrying out of the repression by erecting this same obstacle within itself. It borrowed strength to do this, so to speak, from the father, and this loan was an extraordinarily momentous act.

[Note to self: Freud uses ego ideal and super ego interchangeably, whereas for Delezue they are subtly distinct.]

As you can see from this story, the super ego stands in an ambivalent relationship to the ego.  It is both an image to aspire to and identify with, as well as a threat of destruction that appears to come from outside the ego, even if, like the ego proposing to control the id, it is carried internally as a newly differentiated layer of the ego.  It is the consciousness of wanting to kill your dad and sleep with your mom, as well as the repression of this consciousness.  The latter accounts for why we are not directly conscious of the super ego; its very creation depends on being hidden through an unconscious internalization that identifies the deepest drives of the id as the things most distant from 'us' ( our ego). 

All that remains now is for us to combine our discussion of Freud's opposed instincts with what we learned about the three parts of the psyche.  This brings us finally to chapter 4 of The Ego and the Id, which is the reference of the footnote on pg. 111 of Difference & Repetition.  Yeah, all this for a freaking footnote.

It is natural that we should turn with interest to enquire whether there may not be instructive connections to be traced between the structures we have assumed to exist—the ego, the super-ego and the id—on the one hand and the two classes of instincts on the other; and, further, whether the pleasure principle which dominates mental processes can be shown to have any constant relation both to the two classes of instincts and to these differentiations which we have drawn in the mind.

We can see the main point of contact between Freud's instincts and his structures if we note the odd change in the sexual instincts that happens with the differentiation of the super ego.  When the ego narcissistically substitutes itself for the lost love object, it desexualizes the erotic energy that was invested in or bound to that object.  The moms goes from being a sex object, to being a part of our ego we identify with.  Himself is transformed from erotic rival for her affections into a special moral prohibition against consummating these.  This is the origin of Freudian sublimation, a theory that explains all the 'higher' impulses, like religion or philosophy or art, as the result of a transformation of originally sexual energy.   Once desexualized, the objects that made us horny become sublime expressions of our inner essence.

The transformation of object-libido into narcissistic libido which thus takes place obviously implies an abandonment of sexual aims, a desexualization—a kind of sublimation, therefore. Indeed, the question arises, and deserves careful consideration, whether this is not the universal road to sublimation, whether all sublimation does not take place through the mediation of the ego, which begins by changing sexual object-libido into narcissistic libido and then, perhaps, goes on to give it another aim.

However, this transformation is more than just the substitution of one sexual object, even a more sublime one, for another.  It brings into play the qualitative difference between the two instincts.  The desexualization has the effect of unbinding the sexual energy from any object, creating exactly the free and mobile excitation that we saw was in need of binding in order to begin formation of the ego and the the organization of the id.  Freud believes that this creates a neutral and displaceable energy, no longer necessarily tied to either Eros or Thanatos, but now available for either instinct.  In fact, it's at just this point that the two opposing instincts can become unbalanced, so to speak, and appear to us separately (defused as Freud calls it) rather than locked in their usual cycle of fluctuation around equilibrium.  

The new displaceable energy may serve a 'higher' purpose like thinking which (we presume) strives to bind together a unity and reinforce the ego.

If this displaceable energy is desexualized libido, it may also be described as sublimated energy; for it would still retain the main purpose of Eros—that of uniting and binding—in so far as it helps towards establishing the unity, or tendency to unity, which is particularly characteristic of the ego. If thought-processes in the wider sense are to be included among these displacements, then the activity of thinking is also supplied from the sublimation of erotic motive forces.

Or it may end up augmenting the death instinct which seeks the annihilation of the ego and a return to dust.

The other case will be recollected, in which the ego deals with the first object cathexes of the id (and certainly with later ones too) by taking over the libido from them into itself and binding it to the alteration of the ego produced by means of identification. The transformation [of erotic libido] into ego-libido of course involves an abandonment of sexual aims, a desexualization. In any case this throws light upon an important function of the ego in its relation to Eros. By thus getting hold of the libido from the object cathexes, setting itself up as sole love object, and de-sexualizing or sublimating the libido of the id, the ego is working in opposition to the purposes of Eros and placing itself at the service of the opposing instinctual impulses. It has to acquiesce in some of the other object cathexes of the id; it has, so to speak, to participate in them. We shall come back later to another possible consequence of this activity of the ego.  

This quote becomes much clearer if we include the later consequence it refers to:

It is remarkable that the more a man checks his aggressiveness towards the exterior the more severe—that is aggressive—he becomes in his ego ideal. The ordinary view sees the situation the other way round: the standard set up by the ego ideal seems to be the motive for the suppression of aggressiveness. The fact remains, however, as we have stated it: the more a man controls his aggressiveness, the more intense becomes his ideal's inclination to aggressiveness against his ego. It is like a displacement, a turning round upon his own ego. But even ordinary normal morality has a harshly restraining, cruelly prohibiting quality. It is from this, indeed, that the conception arises of a higher being who deals out punishment inexorably.

I cannot go further in my consideration of these questions without introducing a fresh hypothesis. The super-ego arises, as we know, from an identification with the father taken as a model. Every such identification is in the nature of a desexualization or even of a sublimation. It now seems as though when a transformation of this kind takes place, an instinctual defusion occurs at the same time. After sublimation the erotic component no longer has the power to bind the whole of the destructiveness that was combined with it, and this is released in the form of an inclination to aggression and destruction. This defusion would be the source of the general character of harshness and cruelty exhibited by the ideal—its dictatorial 'Thou shalt'. 

Freud hypothesizes that the conflict between Eros and Thanatos stretches back to time immemorial.  But over and over again he finds it difficult to find examples of the death instinct in action.  He will associate our outwardly aggressive and destructive instinct with it.

It appears that, as a result of the combination of unicellular organisms into multicellular forms of life, the death instinct of the single cell can successfully be neutralized and the destructive impulses be diverted on to the external world through the instrumentality of a special organ. This special organ would seem to be the muscular apparatus; and the death instinct would thus seem to express itself—though probably only in part—as an instinct of destruction directed against the external world and other organisms

But he knows that this is a pretty weak argument.  We don't need anything as strange as the death instinct to explain why I'm going to mow down the next numb nuts who fails to signal a left hand turn.  The pleasure principle more than suffices for that.  The question of the death instinct only becomes acute when our violence is directed at ourselves.  This, finally, provides the connection between the death instinct and the super ego.  The desexualized energy that is freed up alongside the differentiation of the super ego can now be turned back against the ego, and pointedly reveal what for Freud was there all along -- the death instinct.  The ego's narcissistic substitution of itself as erotic object creates an unbound energy capable of sweeping away the very ego we started with.  Synthesis #3

------- 

After that detour through Freud, we're prepared to read the next few pages.  In fact, Deleuze follows Freud's scheme fairly closely.  However, as we already pointed out above, for Deleuze, the death instinct isn't a hidden force operating from the beginning, eternally in conflict with the life instinct.  Instead, the death instinct is synthesized as the third synthesis of time.  It is produced by the same mechanism of narcissistic reflection Freud describes (minus the Oedipus complex baggage).  It also corresponds to an unbinding of energy and a dissolution or fracturing or differentiation of the ego.  But, unlike Freud's material model of death as equilibrium, what's repeated here is the process of unbinding itself.  The death instinct simply is the liberation of energetic difference become unbound: "this energy does not serve Thanatos, it constitutes him".  Deleuze has constructed it as a reflection of a reflection that empties it of any content or memory that would serve as model, and identifies the ego with nothing more than the process of its own construction (and destruction).

The death instinct does not enter into a cycle with Eros, but testifies to a completely different synthesis. It is by no means the complement or antagonist of Eros, nor in any sense symmetrical with him. The correlation between Eros and Mnemosyne is replaced by that between a narcissistic ego without memory, a great amnesiac, and a death instinct desexualised and without love. The narcissistic ego has no more than a dead body, having lost the body at the same time as the objects. It is by means of the death instinct that it is reflected in the ego ideal and has a presentiment of its end in the superego, as though in two fragments of the fractured I. It is this relation between the narcissistic ego and the death instinct that Freud indicated so profoundly in saying that there is no reflux of the libido on to the ego without it becoming desexualised and forming a neutral displaceable energy, essentially capable of serving Thanatos.

Like many of Deleuze's ideas, we can consider this a subtle modification of another philosopher.  Instead of putting Thanatos at the beginning, in conflict with Eros, he puts it at the end.  As a result, instead of repeating an original inorganic equilibrium, death repeats the process of change.  Of course, that subtle difference changes everything.  Death is no longer the end the opposite of life, but its ongoing transformation.  The (non)-being that death implies is no longer the negation of life, but becomes the symbol of a process that can produce many lives, all the intersubjective moments of our life.  And we've already seen what type of being a process has -- a (non)-being without negation, ?-being, the being of questions and problems.  

For death cannot be reduced to negation, neither to the negative of opposition nor to the negative of limitation. It is neither the limitation imposed by matter upon mortal life, nor the opposition between matter and immortal life, which furnishes death with its prototype. Death is, rather, the last form of the problematic, the source of problems and questions, the sign of their persistence over and above every response, the 'Where?' and 'When?' which designate this (non)-being where every affirmation is nourished.

I wish I could better convey the sense of climax I read in this passage.  It's taken such a long time to reach a fuller understanding of it that I've made it seem plodding and arcane.  But Deleuze is actually going very very fast here, moving through the elaborate structure that he's built on top of psychoanalysis to reach this new concept of death.  To me this lends a great depth to what might seem a simple phrase.  Death is a question.  It's the question.  About what difference life makes.  It's not about the end.  It's not about the afterlife opposed to this one.  It's about here and now, about how we live today, constantly dying and being reborn in the perpetual present.  It's a question of how we become alive to ourselves as a process of continual transformation. 

Thursday, May 14, 2020

The Synthesis of Death 1

In what feels like a crescendo of sorts, Deleuze uses this next section (pgs. 108-112) to recapitulate the first two passive syntheses, and discuss again how they lead us to a third synthesis.  I said quite a lot about the third, disjunctive, synthesis when we saw it for the first time framed in terms of Kant's discovery of the transcendental.  In fact, it looks as if all the January and February posts discussed different aspects of it.  Embedded in this new psychoanalytic context though, we'll see that it also relates directly to the Freudian idea of a death drive.  Of course, its meaning will be completely transformed by Deleuze.  Death becomes a symbol of the spiritual annihilation of our ego as a substantial identity, and the condition for our liberation.  In effect, it becomes the final step in answering the question: "How do you make a self?" -- a self capable of posing exactly this question.

First, the recapitulation.

The first synthesis was Habitus -- repetition as habit, as the binding of difference to a form.  This form seeks to repeat itself.  A little feedback loop is created that defines a passive local ego.  The loop defines pleasure as the narcissistic pleasure of existing, and always seeks to perpetuate that pleasure as the principle of its continued existence.  

The second synthesis was what we were calling memory, and is here relabeled Eros-Mnemosyne.  In this case, it's not a form, but a process that is repeated.  This was the process of displacement and disguise that we struggled for so long to figure out -- the displacement of a virtual object into the disguises of real objects.   As the name suggests, we might look at the second synthesis as two distinct syntheses, both of which join together the passive local egos created in the first synthesis.  

On one side, these little egos -- which were conjured into existence by the world's habit of repeating itself, a habit they narcissistically hallucinated was actually all about them -- can be combined by positing a world out there that provides the stuff they need for their collective reproduction.  This is an synthesis of a larger ego based on hypothesizing a reality that would satisfy the various drives to repeat of all its smaller parts.  The search for reality then activates that ego and accounts for all our activity.

On the other side, the little egos can be combined in a second level of passive synthesis.  In this case, the thing that holds them together isn't the hypothesis of a real object that would collectively satisfy them, but the contemplation of a virtual object.  The virtual object is not some specific thing the larger ego wants, but is more like the process by which our wanting attaches to particular real objects.  What's repeated is the hidden process of desiring, of desire motivated by some pure memory that we never actually lived as a present, and played out in the endless succession of real objects that stand in for this missing memory.  In other words, what's repeated is the construction of an ego with sexual drives.    

Together these two sides define two ways of getting pleasure for the larger ego, which is why Deleuze calls them the "ground" of the pleasure principle.  Either the pleasure of actively seeking the real objects that provide for our self-preservation (this pleasure of self-fulfillment was local, instantaneous, and passive in the first synthesis).  Or the sexual pleasure of passively contemplating the virtual object, a pleasure rooted in phantasy that reflects the possible ways the little narcissistic local egos might be joined together.  

The pleasure principle here receives new conditions, as much in regard to a produced reality as to a constituted sexuality. Drives, which are defined only as bound excitation, now appear in differenciated form: as self-preservative drives following the active line of reality, as sexual drives in this new passive extension.

The second synthesis as a whole involves the combination of these two sides locked in a pattern of circulation.  The virtual objects of our sexual desire are abstracted from our past experiences and then projected back onto the real objects around us, imbuing our experience of these with a secret sexual dimension we are constantly grasping for.  But there's no original moment in this cycle, no first real objective memory or virtual object that sets it off.  It's just an always-already operating and never-ending cycle of the displacement of the virtual object onto a new real one, and the disguises of the real objects that hide the virtual one.

If the first makes use of repetition in order to draw off a difference, the second passive synthesis includes difference at the heart of repetition, since the two figures of difference, movement and disguise - the displacement which symbolically affects the virtual object and the disguises which affect, in imaginary fashion, the real objects in which it is incorporated - have become the elements of repetition itself.

The 'never-seen' which characterises an always displaced and disguised object is immersed in the 'already-seen' of the pure past in general, from which that object is extracted. We do not know when or where we have seen it, in accordance with the objective nature of the problematic; and ultimately, it is only the strange which is familiar and only difference which is repeated. 

At this point we come to the third synthesis.  

The problem is basically that the two parts of the second synthesis, which imply a qualitative difference or divergence between the real and the virtual, are easy to misinterpret as converging on some more abstract object that includes both of them as parts or aspects.  In short, it's easy to mistake the process of the second synthesis for a thing, and to then to interpret its movement as a single circle that alternates between two opposed sides of that thing.

In relation to the first passive synthesis of Habitus, the series of the real (or the presents which pass in the real) and the series of the virtual (or of a past which differs in kind from any present) form two divergent circular lines, two circles or even two arcs of the same circle. But in relation to the object = x taken as the immanent limit of the series of virtuals, and as the principle of the second passive synthesis, these are the successive presents of the reality which now forms coexistent series, circles or even arcs of the same circle. It is inevitable that the two references become confused, the pure past assuming thereby the status of a former present, albeit mythical, and reconstituting the illusion it was supposed to denounce, resuscitating the illusion of an original and a derived, of an identity in the origin and a resemblance in the derived.  Moreover, Eros leads its life as a cycle, or as an element within a cycle, where the opposing element can only be Thanatos at the base of memory, the two combining like love and hate, construction and destruction, attraction and repulsion. Always the same ambiguity on the part of the ground: to represent itself in the circle that it imposes on what it grounds, to return as an element in the circuit of representation that it determines in principle.

The mythical present he is referring to here is obviously Plato's metempsychotic heaven.  We saw how Plato's myth seemed at first to involve a deep connection between movement and thought, but that in the end, the movement it imagined was just a simple circle that kept passing through a fixed Platonic heaven before falling back to earth.  Plato's scheme involved movement, but no real qualitative change -- he failed to really introduce time into thought.

Similarly, we can mistake the circulation we described in the second synthesis for a process that always tends to converge towards some master virtual object.  We would never quite grasp this full virtual object since it is inherently partial and in motion, but we can imagine the limit of convergence of the series of disguises and displacements the virtual objects undergo.  Every time we go searching for what we desire, we find it slipping away from us.  Every time we get what we wanted we discover it doesn't quite satisfy us.  Eventually, we become wise to this wild goose chase, and realize that there is no-thing we truly desire at the bottom of it but ourselves.  Ultimately, the limit the process converges to -- "the object = x taken as the immanent limit of the series of virtuals" -- is us, our big ego.  It's our self that keeps this perpetual motion machine in constant circulation.  We never reach all those virtual objects we so lust after because they are simply the masks and disguises of our self.  Because each one is an intersubjective series of possible selves, all the virtual objects can converge on the limit of our real self.

So the third synthesis really functions a sort of corrective to a danger presented by the second.  We could phrase this in buddhist terms and say that the danger lies in mistaking the process by which your self arises for your self as substantive thing.  Overcoming the danger does not involve denouncing the self as mere illusion.  It means experiencing the self as a process, and the way this process is qualitatively different from the things it produces as a residue -- namely, our individual selves considered at each moment, or some abstract and permanent self as soul that functions like a mythical moment.

The essentially lost character of virtual objects and the essentially disguised character of real objects are powerful motivations of narcissism. However, it is by interiorising the difference between the two lines and by experiencing itself as perpetually displaced in the one, perpetually disguised in the other, that the libido returns or flows back into the ego and the passive ego becomes entirely narcissistic. The narcissistic ego is inseparable not only from a constitutive wound but from the disguises and displacements which are woven from one side to the other, and constitute its modification. The ego is a mask for other masks, a disguise under other disguises.

Repetition, in the second synthesis, already included difference within itself.  We understand the process through establishing relations amongst the products which hide or disguise it, but we never get to the process as a thing-in-itself since it is always displaced into these products -- movement and change are built into the repetition of the process.  But now this difference, the movement of displacement and disguise, will be interiorized inside us.  The virtual object we end up passively contemplating is ourself.  And what motivates us to action is just this self disguised in real objects.  We as a whole are the difference and relation between these two.

At first it's not clear what the third synthesis adds to the second beyond a reminder not to confuse the virtual object with a mythical real one.  But actually, 'identifying' ourselves with this process that inherently involves two sides has some pretty strange consequences, precisely because this process is not an identity.  Not only is the virtual object always a non-identity, but the process, considered as a virtual object itself, is built on the non-identity of its virtual and real sides.  In other words, there's a recursive split-that-keeps-on-splitting at the heart of ourselves.  This takes us straight back to Kant's discovery of the fractured I and the transcendental.  

Nevertheless, the importance of the reorganisation which takes place at this level, in opposition to the preceding stage of the second synthesis, cannot be overstated. For while the passive ego becomes narcissistic, the activity must be thought. This can occur only in the form of an affection, in the form of the very modification that the narcissistic ego passively experiences on its own account. Thereafter, the narcissistic ego is related to the form of an I which operates upon it as an 'Other'. This active but fractured I is not only the basis of the superego but the correlate of the passive and wounded narcissistic ego, thereby forming a complex whole that Paul Ricoeur aptly named an 'aborted cogito'.

Gradually, we realize that the virtual objects we experience passively -- as if they were given to us from the past -- as the source of our sexual desires are just versions of our self embedded or embodied in (and abstracted from) the real objects we go chasing after.  But if we take our self as the virtual object we actually love, where did this self come from?  And what action does this object motivate us to, or what real objects would that activity seek?  Now, the activity becomes thinking, and the real objects are thoughts.  With the second passive synthesis, the activity would have been something more like eating or bonking, and the objects would have been apples or babes with beautiful ankles.  The third passive synthesis has the same structure, but moves us up a level.  Instead of searching for our lost loves in the world, we are searching for our self, and we find it given to ourself in our thoughts, but as a gift that comes from outside of us.  There's not original self beyond this process of searching for ourselves.

Now we can start to see the answer to our original koan, "how do you make a self capable of asking this question?"  The structure is tricky to describe because it has a strange self-referential feedback loop.  But then what other structure would account for the our ability to ask this question?  Essentially, the third synthesis is born of the second synthesis looking itself in the mirror.  Since the second synthesis already involved a mirrored virtual object things quickly get pretty complicated.  

Taking a cue from the last time I tried to describe this structure, when it appeared on pg. 86, we should start by emphasizing that there are two sides, each of which are split in two.  We can look at the second passive synthesis either as the construction of an extended passive ego, or as the construction of a large active ego.  It is meant to account for both.  It does this by relating each of them to two sides -- the real and the virtual -- that only stand up by leaning on one another.  The extended passive ego contemplates virtual objects extracted from the relations of real ones.  The active ego pursues real objects that have become invested with virtual significance.  The qualitative split between real and virtual therefore applies to how both egos are constructed, since they are co-constructed.  We can look at the interlocking of virtual and real either as constitutive of either the passion of our desire, or as its activity

So when we say that in the third synthesis, the extended passive ego takes itself as a virtual object, this object is actually better thought of as composed of both a virtual and real part.  The passive being of our ego is synthesized through contemplating their relation.  Likewise, if the active ego takes itself as a real object, this object is also better understood as composed of both real and virtual parts.  The active thinking of our I is similarly synthesized from seeking out their relation.  This is why Deleuze speaks of "the passive and wounded narcissistic ego" on the one hand, and the "fractured I" on the other.  Both recognize themselves as split between the two sides that composed the second synthesis.  In the third synthesis, they also recognize one another as 'the same', as doubles, as if the image in the mirror came to life.  Since the active and passive sides are really co-constructed, the split between real and virtual applies not only to each of them separately, but to both of them together.

This peculiar self-reflexive structure casts our earlier discussion of the "empty form of time", its "pure formal order" of before, during, and after, in a new light.  We called this "unhinged" time because is wasn't measured by the number of times we passed a given point on a circular orbit.  Instead, what's repeated every time is literally nothing, emptiness.  The first synthesis repeated a form or product.  The second synthesis repeated a process that produced multiple products.  With the feedback loop created by the third synthesis, we discover that the product is a process, the process a product, and the distinction between the two is abolished (or perhaps it would be better to say that the difference remains, but becomes relative).  I guess you could equally well look at this and say that it's all product, but Deleuze seems to take the opposite approach and emphasize how it's all process.  So when the extended passive ego of the second synthesis takes itself as a narcissistic object of contemplation, we end up with a pure and never-ending process that produces no products -- the empty form of time.  In the third synthesis, what's repeated is repetition itself.

We saw above that the fracture of the I was no more than the pure and empty form of time, separated from its content. The narcissistic ego indeed appears in time, but does not constitute a temporal content: the narcissistic libido, the reflux of the libido into the ego, abstracts from all content. The narcissistic ego is, rather, the phenomenon which corresponds to the empty form of time without filling it, the spatial phenomenon of that form in general

Though it's empty of any content, this time still has a well defined form.  We might call it the form of a process.  After all, part of the reason I keep using the word process is because it's something that inherently involves time and change.   Boiled way down, this just means that there must be a before and an after, and that they must be qualitatively different, yet somehow still joined as two parts of the process of time passing.   But of course these are just the two sides of the second synthesis, the real and the virtual, which are joined as different but necessary to one another, as 'the same', by the third synthesis.  So now not only is the narcissistic ego seen as empty, a pure process, but its form is seen as the formal static order of time.  This brings us straight back to our discussion of Hamlet (aka Oedipus), and the strange way he became capable of the great act that defines him in an obscure off-stage sea voyage.  

The formal static order of before, during and after marks the division of the narcissistic ego in time, or the conditions of its contemplation. The whole of time is gathered in the image of the formidable action as this is simultaneously presented, forbidden and predicted by the superego: the action=x. The temporal series designates the confrontation of the divided narcissistic ego with the whole of time or the image of the action. The narcissistic ego repeats once in the form of the before or lack, in the form of the Id (this action is too big for me); a second time in the form of an infinite becoming-equal appropriate to the ego ideal; a third time in the form of the after which realises the prediction of the superego (the id and the ego, the condition and the agent, will themselves be annihilated)!

Finally, the form of the passive narcissistic ego is associated with the image of an action, just as we saw the second synthesis had an active and a passive side.  Now though, the action we're talking about is thought.  So here we get a first glimpse of what we'll talk about in the next chapter, the image of thought.  The activity must be thought when the ego takes itself as a narcissistic object.  The image of this activity is the same as the formal order of time -- a caesura that rejoins two sides as qualitatively different.

Well, we didn't get as far as promised at the beginning of the post; the death instinct doesn't enter till the next paragraph in the text.  But I think we've at least got a much better handle on how the third synthesis is constructed now.  And we've also kept what is a very abstract structure firmly attached the question Deleuze wants to ask: "how do you make a self?"  You can see this illustrated perfectly in the last quote -- Freud's tripartite structure of the psyche (Id-Ego-SuperEgo) is reinterpreted as the structure of the very particular process by which the full narcissistic ego is constructed.  For Freud, this is a mainly a structural description of the mind, though he does talk some about its childhood development.  For Deleuze though, since this is also a description of the process of time unfolding, the scheme becomes completely dynamic.  Where Freud wants to know how we make a 'normal' self once and for all, Deleuze is interested in how me make a new self all the time.  Next time we'll investigate his answer, which basically boils down to, "die and be reborn every instant".  

Friday, May 8, 2020

Little Big Man

There's one more thing we can get out of the section ending on pg. 108, and that's a brief translation of the way Deleuze uses size as a technical term.  At the end of this section he goes back to the question of whether the conscious and the unconscious are in opposition, or whether they are just structured differently.  Often we presume that the unconscious looks just like the conscious, except it's dark, so we can't see what's in there very clearly.  Even Freud's dynamic unconscious -- the truly repressed and not merely the pre-conscious -- is actually a lot like regular consciousness.  It's filled with images, with memories of events, with objects that it wants.  We can't find these easily because there is some force hiding them, but the idea seems to be that we'll recognize what's in the unconscious when we finally get a good look at it.  Oh, I wanted to sleep with my mom.

We already know that Deleuze thinks this apparent opposition is actually a secondary factor created by the fact that the two systems are structured in completely different ways.  Consciousness represents the complete and stable identities of real objects.  The unconscious contemplates the various disguises and constant displacement of virtual objects.  The latter deals with differences that cannot be fully represented.  The virtual object is never complete, only partial; never self-identical, but always paradoxically missing from dis-place.  For that reason it always requires a series of real terms for its definition.  Deleuze will often characterize these differences at work in the unconscious as "little".

To ask whether the unconscious is ultimately oppositional or differential, an unconscious of great forces in conflict or one of little elements in series, one of opposing great representations or differenciated little perceptions, appears to resuscitate earlier hesitations and earlier polemics between the Leibnizian tradition and the Kantian tradition.

And last time we saw him mention that "the ontological bearing of problems and questions" was expressed as "repeat a little".

Obviously, "little" here doesn't mean that something is just quantitatively smaller.  It is being qualitatively opposed to "great".  Used this way it carries more of the sense of partial, unfinished, etc ...  We repeat the question "a little" because it's impossible to repeat the whole thing, since it is not, in fact, a thing that could be repeated and integer number of times.  The perceptions are "little" because they are the perceptions of parts, in the sense that they are the part's perceptions. 

We've already met these perceptions; they were the passive, partial, larval, local egos of the first synthesis.  Which helps to partially answer a question that came up for me at the time.  If the problem of this chapter is how to construct and identity in a world of difference (to which the answer is repetition), then how does talking about little egos in every, "rat in the labyrinth and to ever muscle of the rat" get us anywhere?  Aren't we in danger of reintroducing the same unity we were trying to derive?  It could be that on some level we are.  I think Deleuze's concept of repetition is constructed repetitively, through the relation of three different concepts of repetition, which suggests a sort of bootstrapping effect or feedback loop of some sort.  But that's for later.  Right now, the idea is that the little egos are qualitatively different from the great ego because they are partial, not total, and passive, not active, productive processes, not products.  They are essentially virtual, which is perhaps part of why he calls the pleasure of their auto-satisfaction "hallucinatory".

The fact that these egos should be immediately narcissistic is readily explained if we consider narcissism to be not a contemplation of oneself but the fulfilment of a self-image through the contemplation of something else: the eye or the seeing ego is filled with an image of itself in contemplating the excitation that it binds. It produces itself or 'draws itself' from what it contemplates (and from what it contracts and invests by contemplation). This is why the satisfaction which flows from binding is necessarily a 'hallucinatory' satisfaction of the ego itself, even though hallucination here in no way contradicts the effectivity of the binding.

In short, even if there is a sort of self-similar fractal structure to the concept of repetition, the form of each level is different.  Call it a qualitative, rather than a quantitative fractal, if that makes any sense.  So when Deleuze introduces passive local little egos, he is not just begging his own question, but is showing us another level that involves a different set of forces that can serve as an invisible-hand explanation of identity or repetition at the macro level.

This discussion reminded me of Todd May's remarks about the molecular and the molar, macro and micro politics, in his introduction to Deleuze. 

To embrace the concept of the machine is to move from a focus on the macropolitical to the micropolitical, from the molar to the molecular.The distinction between these two pairs of terms is one of the most misunderstood in Deleuze's thought.

Deleuze and Guattari write, "the molecular, or microeconomics, micropolitics, is defined not by the smallness of its elements but by the nature of its 'mass' – the quantum flow as opposed to the molar segmented line."  It is not smallness but something else that defines the molecular and micropolitics. The quantum flow as opposed to the molar segmented line. What is a quantum flow? It is what we encountered in the discussion of science. A quantum flow is a virtual field that actualizes itself. It is a machinic process. Genetic information is a quantum flow. An egg is a quantum flow. Matter is a quantum flow, a fact we understand when we subject it to conditions that are far from equilibrium. In physics, quantum theory tries to understand matter as often being subject to chance and unpredictability. Einstein's quarrel with quantum theory concerns precisely this. "God does not play dice with the universe," he said. Oh, but God does, replied the quantum theorists, and Nietzsche and Deleuze with them. There is more to the universe than meets the eye, even the eye of the relativist.  Molar segmented lines: given identities with recognizable borders.Quantum flows: fluid identities that arise from a chaotic and often un-predictable folding, unfolding, and refolding of matter. Micropolitics is not an issue of the small; it is an issue of quantum flows. It is an issue of machines.